Jump to content

Talk:Ross–Littlewood paradox

Page contents not supported in other languages.
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

History

[edit]

This article needs a History section detailing who first proposed it, historical arguments, etc. I have not yet found any good references on the web, but I remember seeing two or three good articles in the past. — Loadmaster 22:14, 6 November 2006 (UTC)[reply]

The first reference now is to a different Ross (Alf Ross) and a different paradox (one from deontic logic), see e.g. Understanding Ross's Paradox by AZIZAH AL-HIBRI, The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy Vol. 10, No. 1 (SPRING, 1979), pp. 163-170 This needs to be fixed! SnoTraveller (talk) 10:55, 30 September 2021 (UTC)[reply]

sci.math newsgroup

[edit]

This problem has been discussed to death on sci.math. I've listed a few of the more recent (2005−2006) threads. — Loadmaster 22:14, 6 November 2006 (UTC)[reply]

Solution

[edit]

The solution is 10-1+10-1+10-1+...

By straightforward arrangement, it is also 1-1+1-1+1-1+...

Therefore, according to Bolzano's Paradoxien des Unendlichen, the serie can be prooved to be any number and the problem has no mathematical solution.

AlainD 08:57, 13 January 2007 (UTC)[reply]

On a sidenote, noon is expected to arrive at 2^(-(n-1)). According to the problem description, n is countably infinite.
Thus, n->infinite. Which means 2^(-(n-1))->0. That is also one point that illustrates that the problem's initial assumptions were problematic, a fact that is intuitively confirmed. (essentially - and if I'm mistaken please post - "how many steps of 9 does it take to count to infinity ?") —Preceding unsigned comment added by 87.202.27.214 (talk) 02:44, 7 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
The "straightforward arrangement" is flawed. Even for a convergent series if you rearrange terms you can change the nature of convergence. It's even more the case for divergent series. 10-1+10-1+10-1+... diverges to positive infinity, whereas by contrast 1-1+1-1+1-1+... oscillates and is Cesaro summable to 1/2. See Summation of Grandi's series for various summation methods and the differences between them and their results.
Also, Bolzano didn't have the last word on the series; see History of Grandi's series. He shouldn't be cited as an authority on what the series means. I'm deleting this section from the article. Melchoir (talk) 23:45, 15 July 2008 (UTC)[reply]

Article title

[edit]

Would this article not be more accurated titled Ross-Littlewood paradox? Also, Supertask#Ross-Littlewood_paradox contains more good information than this article; some content really should be moved to here, leaving a shorter summary in the Supertask article. ~ Booya Bazooka 04:01, 25 January 2007 (UTC)[reply]

That's probably the best approach, to merge this article with Supertask#Ross-Littlewood_paradox into a new Ross-Littlewood paradox aticle. Then the contents of the section in Supertask can be condensed, being replaces with a "Main article" link to the new article. — Loadmaster 22:01, 15 February 2007 (UTC)[reply]

References in BJPS

[edit]

The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science has two relevant publications regarding this topic:

  • "On Some Paradoxes of the Infinite". Victor Allis; Teunis Koetsier. Vol. 42, No. 2. (Jun., 1991), pp. 187-194.
  • "Ross' Paradox Is an Impossible Super-Task". Jean Paul Van Bendegem. Vol. 45, No. 2. (Jun., 1994), pp. 743-748.

Electronic versions are available on JSTOR if you have access to it. ~ Booya Bazooka 04:28, 25 January 2007 (UTC)[reply]

I went ahead and added those two references to the "References" section of the article. They need to be wikified into ref form, though. — Loadmaster 17:19, 22 February 2007 (UTC)[reply]

The Lamp Paradox

[edit]

Shouldn't there be a mentioning of the Lamp Paradox? It is basicily the same as the Vase Paradox, it goes at follows: "Let there be a Lamp which can have two states: "on" or "off". At t=1 the lamp is off, t=1/2 the lamp switches on, t=1/4 the lamp switches off and so on. The question posed is: what will the state of the lamp be at t=0?"

One of the suggested answers is that the lamp is neither on nor off, because it never reaches t=0. Maest 20:19, 4 March 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Well, the two problems are similar, but they are not the same. The first asks for the final sum of balls based on adding and removing them from the vase, while the second asks what the "final" state of the lamp will be. The first question can be answered assuming that the time t=0 can be defined well enough. The second cannot be answered because even if time t=0 is defined, the answer relies on knowing the "last" step prior to t=0, when the lamp was switched on or off for the "last" time. The first problem needs no "last" step to be answered. It would be nice to have a "Lamp Paradox" article that could be added to the "See also" section, though. — Loadmaster 00:31, 6 March 2007 (UTC)[reply]
I found the article, named Thomson's lamp, for the paradox you describe. I've added it to the "See also" section appropriately. And I added a redirect for Lamp paradox as well. — Loadmaster

Pearl of Wisdom

[edit]

A variation of the Balls and Vase problem is the Pearl of Wisdom. An example of the tale can be found at www.246.dk/pearl.html. — Loadmaster 22:03, 13 August 2007 (UTC)[reply]

The link has disappeared, but can still be found in the WayBack Machine archive here or here. — Loadmaster (talk) 02:14, 8 February 2011 (UTC)[reply]

My 2 cents

[edit]

I think this problem simply shows that you have to be careful about your terms - in particular, when talking about limits, you have to define your topology first.

The problem can be phrased like this: We have a function f from [0,1] to some state space of the vase, let's call it X. We have defined f on a sequence converging to 1 and would like to know the continuous continuation.

If we let X be the one-point compactification of the real numbers and f(1-2^-n)=9n, then the limit is infinity.

On the other hand, if we let X be (each component representing the presence or absence of an individual marble) with the product topology or in other words the topology of pointwise convergence, and f(1)=(1,1,...,1,0,...) (10 ones, then zeroes) and f(2)=(0,1,1,...,1,0,...) (0, then 19 ones, then zeroes) and so on, then the limit is the zero sequence, since every component pointwisely converges to zero.

You see, it's just a matter of proper definitions. If there is a notable source for this argument, I strongly suggest adding it to the article. Functor salad 04:10, 16 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Benardete's Paradox

[edit]

Another variation is Benardete's paradox, said to be an extension of Zeno's Paradox, which is described at thinkquest.org. Briefly, the god Zeus decides to kill Prometheus by issuing an order to an infinitude of his demons, ordering the first demon to kill Prometheus if he is not dead by 2:00, the second to kill him if he is not dead at 1:30, the third to kill him if he is not dead at 1:15, etc., each demon killing Prometheus in half the time interval of the subsequent demon. The strangeness comes in the realization that Prometheus is indeed dead by 2:00, but yet no specific demon killed him. — Loadmaster (talk) 04:11, 30 March 2008 (UTC)[reply]

Fake question

[edit]

Just like that infamous lamp, this question is a mathematical/philosophical/logical question masquerading as a physical one. Obviously when you're talking infinities, "balls" and "vases" are just placeholder concepts: the number of physical operations that can be performed in a finite time is finite. Casting this problem in physical terms is not valid. A more honest question is "what is the limit of the infinite sum "10 - 1 + 10 -1 ..."; this question can be mathematically discussed. A question of balls and vases falls at the basic hurdle of making physical sense. --Slashme (talk) 15:33, 27 May 2008 (UTC)[reply]

Since the best evidence so far is that the Universe is composed of discrete matter-energy/time-space quantum "units", any mathematical problem dealing with continuous functions, real numbers, or infinities is bound to fail to make total sense as physical reality. — Loadmaster (talk) 00:01, 28 May 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Actually, some proponents of hypercomputation are hoping that at some point in the future there will be actual, physical computers performing infinitely many operations (in sequence) in a finite amount of time: a physical Zeno machine. —Preceding unsigned comment added by 128.113.89.96 (talk) 15:21, 28 May 2008 (UTC)[reply]
Well, when that time comes about, it'll be interesting to see what result comes out. From Wikiquote:
We all know Linux is great…it does infinite loops in 5 seconds.
-- Linus Torvalds about the superiority of Linux on the Amsterdam Linux Symposium

--Slashme (talk) 05:21, 30 May 2008 (UTC)[reply]

Original research

[edit]

The Original Research tag is debatable. Set theorists are clearly in agreement that the first answer (zero balls left in the vase) is correct. The other solutions are variations on the conditions and "meaning" of the problem. — Loadmaster (talk) 02:25, 17 August 2009 (UTC)[reply]

Requested move

[edit]

Talk:Balls and vase problemTalk:Ross–Littlewood paradox — This article was moved without moving the corresponding Talk page. The new talk page only has a single edit, the addition of a wikiproject template. ~ Booya Bazooka 00:56, 1 November 2010 (UTC)[reply]

 Done. By the way, it's okay to just use {{db-move}} in clear-cut cases like this. Jafeluv (talk) 13:31, 7 November 2010 (UTC)[reply]

Simple

[edit]

The problem can be stated as <br\><br\> <br\><br\>

The philosophers assuming zero as answer are getting that because they are implying that the two infinities are same. Their logic is: <br\> <br\> and <br\> Hence the two infinities are assumed same! Which obviously aren't!!

People with other answers or variable answer based on which ball is removed are getting there because they are cancelling out unequal infinities somewhere in the process. — Preceding unsigned comment added by VinnieCool (talkcontribs) 01:34, 10 June 2012 (UTC)[reply]

And yet, using standard cardinal arithmetic, 10 0 = ℵ0, i.e., the cardinal number of elements inserted is equal to the number of the elements removed. The two infinities are equal. — Loadmaster (talk) 17:17, 10 August 2013 (UTC)[reply]
So, VinnieCool, some infinities are more equal than other infinities?
I think it logically follows that IF they are UNequal, then one of them can not be INfinite.(edited from "finite"06:46)
Let adding and subtraction of balls take place simultaneus and assume end of operations IS possible (no supertask): then zero balls remain in vase because an infinite number has been removedSintermerte (talk) 06:40, 22 February 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Section needs rewriting

[edit]

I think the section on the "no balls left in vase" solution needs to be rewritten. It really doesn't make sense on face-- of course there is always a step n at which ball n is removed, but it's just as obvious that at at every step n, nine more balls are added. I'm not trying to argue against inclusion of this section; I just think it needs to be rewritten so that it at least makes some small amount of logical sense on face... I hope this makes sense. Thanks — Preceding unsigned comment added by 70.36.226.136 (talk) 21:50, 1 August 2013 (UTC)[reply]

Indistinguishability and probabalistic behavior

[edit]

I did a quick google search, and I can find no mention of the distinguishability of balls. In physics, the statistics of particles depends on whether the particles are distinguishable or not, i.e. does swapping ball 1 and ball 2 change the state of the system in some way. It seems in this case that the balls are being counted, but with indistinguishable balls, there is no ordering which is unique. It makes no sense to say "I removed the first ball, then the second, then..." since there is no ball #1, 2 or 3. In an indistinguishable case, you can only specify the states of the balls probabalistically. After the first step, there are 10 balls in there, each with a 1/10 probability of being removed. After this, I believe the math gets hairy, since you can't remove a ball you already removed, and thus you need to calculate the probability of each ball being removed given that it was not removed in any previous step. Then you have to do a sum to find the number of balls left 47.21.153.202 (talk) 15:31, 9 August 2013 (UTC)[reply]

I'm not sure, but you seem to be confusing physical reality with abstract mathematics. It's an abstract mathematical/logical gedankenexperiment, wherein we use an infinite number of abstract "balls". We assume each ball is uniquely labeled (e.g., with the natural number reflecting the order in which it is inserted into the vase). Such labeling allows us to keep track of which balls were inserted and which were removed at any given moment during the procedure. Perhaps we need to add some verbiage making it clear that there is a labeling employed, or some other means used to uniquely distinguish between different balls. — Loadmaster (talk) 23:01, 9 August 2013 (UTC)[reply]
I think my suggestion is that, when dealing with inifinites within the context of this problem, the ability to uniquely number the balls is broken. I suggest this due to what I percieve as a kind of "reductio ad absurdium", wherein changing which balls we remove, but not how many, changes how many balls are left in the vase. This challenges that we can uniquely number the balls we put into the vase, which seems to be a major premise of the proposed solutions to the paradox. I suppose my new premise, due to the statement of the problem not explicitly defining how we remove balls from this vase, is that they are removed at random, and that this may lead to a non-self-contradictory solution to the problem. Then again, it may just push the problem off on to how the probabilities are calculated, instead of which ball is removed. My parallel to physics is due to my personal training in physics and total lack of formal or significant informal education in the mathematics of infinites outside the scope of physics, which I can completely understand as significantly hampering my ability to comment on this problem. 47.21.153.202 (talk) 18:15, 12 August 2013 (UTC)[reply]
Your suggestion sounds a lot like the assertion that the Axiom of Choice is required for the infinite case, which is by no means a principle that all mathematicians take for granted. That's actually a very helpful observation for me, but seems a bit out of scope, as it is original research of the solution. 70.247.167.104 (talk) 13:59, 11 February 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Paradox Solved

[edit]

Really I think this paradox should be reported as "solved". I was working to a solution that I unfortunately found to be already published 13 years ago by John Byl On Resolving The Littlewood-Ross Paradox on Missouri Journal of Mathematical Sciences Vol.12 (No. 1, Winter 2000): 42-47. At the end the urn contains an infinite number of balls (9ω), just numbering balls is some misleading. Nerd4j (talk) 09:49, 4 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]

Well, that's the whole problem with the paradox; there is no single solution accepted by everyone. Based on what I read, most mathematicians (logicians and number theorists) accept that, as the problem is usually stated, if each ball n is placed into the urn at some time tn and then removed at a later time t10n (or some similar moment), then after ω steps, every ball has been removed at some point after it was inserted, so there must be no balls left in the urn. Far from being misleading, the numbering of the balls, and more importantly the relative order in which the balls are inserted and removed from the vase, is the crucial point of the whole exercise.
If, however, we accept that there are an infinite number of balls left in the vase, we must ask which balls are left, i.e., what are their numeric labels? If we uniquely label each ball as it is inserted, and there are indeed 9ω balls left in the vase, how do we explain the labels on the balls remaining in the vase following the removals of the first 1ω balls?
In any case, before this turns into a lengthy and inappropriate discussion of the problem, be aware that the article does in fact explain the different interpretations of the problem and its possible resolutions. From that it should be obvious that we can't declare one solution as "the" solution here on WP. — Loadmaster (talk) 20:20, 4 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]
We can only call it solved when scientific consensus on a solution has been reached. Paradoctor (talk) 22:26, 4 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]

In his article Jhon Byl took a very modest approach and left the decision to the reader, but actually he performed a well argumented demonstration about the fact that there is no paradox. This article was then published on the Missouri Journal of Mathematical Sciences (and never contradicted by any other article) which means that it has been accepted by the scientific comunity, on the other hand I was not able to find the paradox explained on any official scientific journal. I'm not good as Byl but I'll try to explain the solution in my own words. So at each instant of time we are putting 10 balls into the urn and taking out one ball. - If the balls we take out are numbered with 10, 20, ... than by noon there is an infinite number of balls left in the urn. - If the balls we take out are numbered with 9, 18, ... than by noon there is an infinite number of balls left in the urn. ... - If the balls we take out are numbered with 2, 4, 6, ... than by noon there is an infinite number of balls left in the urn. The only problem seems to be if we take out the balls in the order 1, 2, 3, 4, ... but the quantity of balls taken (or left) can't depend on the order in which they are taken. We have two possible solutions: the whole human logic is wrong or the 'reductio ad absurdum' is wrong ( I guess we are in the second case :) ). In the paradox we assume each ball to have a label (with a number), by saying this we are defining an order over the set of balls. The set of balls is a 'totally ordered set' and we can define an 'order topology' over such set ([1]). ℕ is an order topology and ω1 = |ℕ| is a 'limit point' for ℕ ([2]) that means that for each x ∈ ℕ, x+1 < ω1 (by def). The interval [0,ω1) defines a space isomorphic to ℕ called 'first countable' ([3]), the interval [ω1,ω2) defines a space called 'second countable', |[0,ω1)| = |[ω1,ω2)| but the two sets are NOT equal, we can make the stronger assumption that [0,ω1) and [ω1,ω2) are disjointed ([0,ω1)∩[ω1,ω2)=∅). For example we can define [ω1,ω2) = { x+2i | x ∈ ℕ }, so the numbers in [ω1,ω2) are complex and therefore for each x ∈ [ω1,ω2), x ∉ ℕ. The same is for [ω2,ω3), [ω3,ω4), ... [ω9,ω10). Returning to the paradox, in each finite instant of time t ∈ ℕ we put the balls labeled in [0,10t) and took the balls labeled in [0,t), so at each finite instant of time t the urn is not empty. By noon we put an infinite number of balls labeled with values in [0,ω10). In the 'reductio ad absurdum' we argument that for each t ∈ ℕ, the ball labeled with t was taken at instant t. By definition ω1 is the limit point of ℕ ( ∀x ∈ ℕ, x+1 < ω1 ) so at each instant of time t we took a ball labeled with a value in [0,ω1), but we put balls labeled in [0,ω10) so all the balls labeled in [ω1,ω10) must be still in the urn. The misunderstanding is given by the fact that the the concept of 'amount' and the concept of 'labeling' are confused. The set of inserted balls is isomorphic to ℕ and the set of balls taken is also isomorphic to ℕ, but the balls taken are a proper subset of the balls inserted. We put all the balls in [0,ω10) (that is numerically isomorphic to ℕ) but we take only the balls in [0,ω1) (that is also numerically isomorphic to ℕ) it means that the urn contains an infinite number if balls labeled in [ω1,ω10). If we accept to be able to perform an infinite number of operations in a finite amount of time, we must accept to be able to put an amount of balls that is more than countable. — Preceding unsigned comment added by Nerd4j (talkcontribs) 11:15, 18 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]

About the Missouri Journal of Mathematical Sciences. I doubt that it is peer-reviewed. Byl's paper has one spurious citation to it. In a future, greatly expanded version of the article, this paper might be included. Currently, it would give WP:UNDUE weight to it. Paradoctor (talk) 16:54, 18 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]
Which is reasonable. Just because a published article has no printed objections in no way implies that its premise is accepted by the mathematics community at large (it implies only that it was deemed suitable for publication at the time). I'll reiterate: the different interpretations of the problem are covered in the article. I'll also reiterate this: the order in which balls are inserted and removed really is the crux of the entire problem; simply declaring that it does not matter ignores the subtle nature of the problem entirely. — Loadmaster (talk) 21:55, 18 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]
You are both right about the pubblications, I don't think the Missouri Journal of Mathematical Sciences is peer-reviewed too, and actually I don't know which is the average competence level in the Central Missouri State University, but in my university each article is reviewed and discussed by doctoral candidates and professors before to be published and I assume that every university follows more or less the same behavior (I may be wrong). When I first read the Ross-Littlewood Paradox it was clear to me that the urn is always full because it follows trivially from the definitions of 'first countable' and 'limit point'. I was going to write an article to argue the overlapping of ℕ as 'definition of countable set' and ℕ as 'order topology' that leads to the misunderstanding. In fact saying that for each x in ℕ, x was taken at instant x is not contradicting the fact that the urn is still full, therefore there is no paradox (that's my personal point of view). Before to start writing the article I searched for some previous work and I found Byl's article that argues the same point of view using the same arguments. So my work wasn't necessary and I didn't even start with it. Nerd4j (talk) 11:46, 19 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]
Responding to Loadmaster: the reductio ad absurdum is possible only if we define a labeling for the balls such that each ball has a unique label, so we are able to identify each ball in the urn, the problem is given by the assumption that all the values used to label the balls belong to ℕ. My argument (and Byl's) is that this assumption is wrong because is contraddicting the definition of 'first countable' and 'limit point'. I know that it's a minority point of view but due to the fact that it leads to a consistent solution of the problem by simply applying well known definitions and concepts I think that it's deserving a further discussion. Nerd4j (talk) 11:46, 19 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]
Not here for the time being, I'm afraid. Please note that solving a paradox requires not only to propose a solution, but also showing how the contradicting approaches are wrong. You might want to find other places where this kind of discussion is appropriate. If you WP:EMAIL me, I'll gladly explain the mistakes in Byl's paper. Regards, Paradoctor (talk) 15:01, 19 November 2013 (UTC)[reply]

Ross Who? Littlewood Who?

[edit]

Who is the paradox named for? 70.247.167.104 (talk) 14:11, 11 February 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Good question. The authors are listed in the "Further reading" section: John E. Littlewood (author of Littlewood's Miscellany, 1953) and Sheldon Ross (author of A First Course in Probability, 1988). A Google search also turned up this document (also here) that lists the same books and authors. I've added some links to the article for them. — Loadmaster (talk) 16:28, 11 February 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Problem description is not precise

[edit]

In the introduction, it is never said how many balls are added or removed at each step. when reading the solution part, we have first "since at every step along the way more balls are being added than removed" but it was never assumed before. that is just a problem of formulation because after it seems obvious that 10 balls are added and 1 is removed at each step. but in the introduction, it seems that the problem is more general, and that any number of balls could be added and removed. 150.65.16.33 (talk) 12:27, 25 June 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Yes, the article at present is a complete (erroneous) mess. The way Littlewood stated it, the answer is quite clear (not that this prevents crank nonsense, which WP seems to require equal attention to); the problem as stated in the article at present has no solution. (But I can't completely understand your comment either...) The article should be rewritten, starting by quoting the problem as posed by Littlewood... I have a copy of the Miscellany somewhere, and keep meaning to do it. Imaginatorium (talk) 15:31, 25 June 2014 (UTC)[reply]
I just edited the description of the task to say "at each step 10 balls are added to the vase and 1 ball removed from it". MaigoAkisame (talk) 13:56, 19 April 2017 (UTC)[reply]
Oh, I realized the text already contained this sentence in a different place. I removed the original sentence, so the effect of my edit is moving it to a place which makes the text more coherent. MaigoAkisame (talk) 15:23, 19 April 2017 (UTC)[reply]

I would also like to highlight the fact that the problem posed does not specify what the vase's volume is...PersistantCorvid (talk) 01:24, 21 August 2017 (UTC)[reply]

Figure vs Problem Description

[edit]

The problem description adds the first balls at 11:59:30, while the figure adds the first balls at 11:59:00. The figure matches the description in Ross, so I think the problem description should be changed. Additionally, the problem structure is perhaps better revealed by this chart:

Illustration of the Ross-Littlewood problem description (following Ross).

Cerberus (talk) 15:48, 19 September 2017 (UTC)[reply]

Where could this go in the article?

[edit]

The "Vase is empty" solution uses this logic: "This means that by noon, every ball labeled n that is inserted into the vase is eventually removed in a subsequent step."

Now consider the question, "at what time, or in which step, is the last ball removed?" The answer is there is no last ball. But I don't think this question can go in that section, because it's not part of the logic leading to this solution. Where could it go? 23.121.191.18 (talk) 06:09, 28 January 2020 (UTC)[reply]

Ross deserves credit ... but NOT for coming up with this paradox

[edit]

Ross, of course, deserves credit for whatever work he did on the problem.

But: The paradox was invented by Littlewood, not Ross. So Ross does not merit having his name attached to the paradox for developing it further, 35 years later!

(Also: The paradox was discussed by Martin Gardner in his Mathematical Games column in Scientific American long before Ross mentioned it.) 2601:200:C000:1A0:18:344C:F94C:B721 (talk) 00:55, 25 March 2022 (UTC)[reply]

Section "depends on the conditions"

[edit]

I propose either moving "depends on the conditions" under "vase is empty" or to a new section about "variants of the problem", since it follows the same logic as the "vase is empty" solution except with similar problems C7XWiki (talk) 05:56, 27 March 2022 (UTC)[reply]