Jump to content

User:ABoogieWitDaHoodie/sandbox

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Anaximenes of Miletus (/ˌænækˈsɪməˌnz/; ‹See Tfd›Greek: Ἀναξιμένης ὁ Μιλήσιος; c. 586 – c. 526 BC) was an Ancient Greek Pre-Socratic philosopher active in the latter half of the 6th century BC.[1][2] The details of his life are obscure and undocumented because none of his work has been preserved. Anaximenes’s ideas and philosophies are known today because of comments made by Aristotle and other writers on the history of Greek Philosophy.[3] Apollodurus noted the dates Anaximander was alive in relation to defining historical events, and estimated Anaximenes’s lifespan to occur in same time period that Cyrus beat Croesus in the Battle of Thymbra in 546 BCE.[2] Some of his writings survived the Hellenistic Age, but no record of these documents currently exist.[2] As one of the three Milesian philosophers that were considered the first revolutionary thinkers of the Western world,[4] he is best known and identified as a younger friend or student of Anaximander.[5][6] Much of his astronomical thought was based off of Anaximander’s, but he altered Anaximander’s astrological ideas to better fit his own philosophical views on physics and the natural world.[2] The Ionian school was the first school on record that encouraged their pupils to constructively criticize their master’s teachings,[7] which aptly demonstrated a tolerance toward new ideas and logic for their time. Thales taught Anaximander, and Anaximander taught Anaximenes.[4] Each philosopher developed a distinct system of cosmology without completely rejecting their teacher’s view of universe or creating major disagreement between them.[7] Anaximenes, like others in his school of thought, practiced material monism.[8][6] This tendency to identify one specific underlying reality made up of a material thing is what Anaximenes is principally known for today. Anaximenes was the last known Milesian philosopher, as Miletus was taken over by the Persian army in 494 BC.[7] Because none of his works contain theological references, there is no evidence as to whether or not he practiced religion or if he was an atheist.[9]

Anaximenes of Miletus
Side view of the head and neck of Anaximenes of Miletus in a circle, all monochrome
Anaximenes of Miletus
Bornc. 586 BC
Diedc. 526 BC
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionAncient Greek city of Miletus (present-day Turkey)
Inhabitant of the Occidental World
SchoolIonian / Milesian
Focused on Naturalism
Main interests
Metaphysics
Notable ideas
Air is the arche

The Universe is in constant motion

Matter changes through rarefaction and condensation

Anaximenes and the Arche

[edit]

While his predecessors Thales and Anaximander proposed that the archai (singular: arche, meaning the underlying material of the world) were water and the ambiguous substance apeiron, respectively, Anaximenes asserted that aer (“mist,” “vapor,” “air”) was this primary substance of which all natural things are made.[10] By rejecting his teacher’s theory based on the concept of discontinuity, Anaximenes took a more empirical approach to understanding the underlying processes of genesis and change on two assumptions: (1) origination retains properties of the aperion, but it has an actually tangible state of existence as air that can evolve other substances and (2) genesis and change depend on a cohesive, mechanistic process known as condensation and rarefaction.[11] He believed that air was infinite and divine.[10] Anaximenes was first to use the word Pneuma (“breath of life”) as a synonym with air.[11] One of the only surviving quotes by Anaximenes reads, “Just as our soul...being air holds us together, so pneuma and air encompass [and guard] the whole world.”[11] The analogy compared atmospheric air as the divine and human air as souls that animate people.[10] This relation of the macroscopic and microscopic suggested Anaximenes believed there was an overarching principle that regulated all life and behavior.[12] Essentially, he thought air was the primary substance that held the Universe together.[10] Interestingly, The Old Testament features a similar analogy to the founding of the world and creation of man, but Anaximenes did not recognize a creator of the universe and did not think the pneuma as a creator to guide man.[11] The choice of air may seem arbitrary, but Anaximenes based his conclusion on naturally observable phenomena in the processes of rarefaction and condensation.[13] The primary difference in the forms of air as matter is the degree of condensation and density.[12] When air condenses it becomes visible, and according to Anaximenes, the spread-out, invisible, infinite air was condensed to wind, then formed into clouds, which condensed further to produce mist, rain, and other forms of precipitation.[12][11] As the condensed air cooled, Anaximenes supposed that Earth itself was an early condensate of air-- the process continued until the air was condensed enough to form solids like the Earth and ultimately stones.[10] By contrast, Anaximenes was able to visually see how water evaporates into air and based his concept of rarefaction on this observation. According to him, any object that held light was made of fire, and fire was made from the rarefaction of air.[10] While other philosophers also recognized such transitions in states of matter, Anaximenes was the first to associate the qualitative change in hot/dry and cold/wet pairings with the density of a single material, effectively adding a quantitative dimension to the Milesian monistic system.[14][15] He attributed condensation to cold/wet air and rarefaction to the interaction of hot/dry air.[10] This concept was the foundation for understanding the existence of different substances, materials, and elements due to their arrangement of atoms and number of subatomic particles.

Influence on Philosophy

[edit]
A painting of Anaximenes of Miletus

Since language and communication were very limited in his time, Anaximenes’s analogies were key in explaining the uncertain through the certain. For example, he knew for certain that blowing air on his hand with his mouth wide open produced hot air, while blowing on his hand with half-closed lips produced cold air.[16] These observations were key in his postulate that the hot air was due to rarefaction and expansion, whereas the cold air was due to condensation and compression. Although in modern times it is known that this is actually the opposite, Anaximenes was key in arriving at this conclusion. His analogies often connected parallels between man and the cosmos, insinuating that the same natural laws observable on earth applied to the heavens.[16] Over 2000 years later, Isaac Newton proved this to be true.[16] Throughout history, Anaximenes’s observations proved helpful to uncover powerful theories, such as quantum physics and chemical properties.[16] By the end of the Milesian philosophy era, there were many questions left unanswered; this sparked the stimulation of Pre-socratic thought to continue through many other notable philosophers such as Pythagoras, Parmenides, Heraclitus, and Democritus.[16]

Anaximenes greatest influence is not from his theories of matter, but instead it is from how he thought about these ideas. For instance, his theory of air being the underlying substance was disproved, but when looking at his idea from a fundamental aspect, in which a substance is capable of changing forms, his theory was the first of its kind.[17] This concept of changing of forms is fundamental to scientific thought and shows how his ideas, although not correct, were helpful in the development of modern views. In the time of Anaximenes, phenomena were usually explained with reference to religion and mythology. Anaximenes explained events like rainbows with concrete ideas instead of saying they were the work of a goddess. The explanation Anaximenes gave helped in the transition of attributing the cause of phenomena to scientific events, rather than mythology.

Anaximenes, Aristotle, and Plato

[edit]
An artist's rendition of Anaximenes of Miletus

Many similarities to Anaximenes’s theories are apparent in Plato’s theory. So much so, that some scholars have said Plato has based his theory of matter on Anaximenes’s theory.[18] In Aristotle’s view on Anaximenes, he interprets the theory as the one substance being air, and all other states of matter are different condensations of air. In Plato’s interpretation of Anaximenes’s theory, he considers the seven states of matter: fire, air, wind, clouds, earth and stone as different densities.[18] Acknowledging that these seven states of matter are different densities shows how the intrinsic properties of the matter have changed, and they are actually different substances. Anaximenes supports this conclusion by his explanation using the concept of felting. Felting is a technological model used to explain condensation, in which wool turns into felt and has new properties.[18] Just as how wind is compressed into clouds in Anaximenes’s theory. Without recognizing Anaximenes’s influence on Plato, and simply focusing on Anaximenes’s influence on Aristotle, Anaximenes’s contributions to scientific thought are not fully recognized. Aristotle interpreted Anaximenes’s theory as all substance being different manifestations of air. It was Plato’s interpretation of Anaximenes’s theory that recognized the fundamental changes of air into other substances.[9][19] And even though Anaximenes’s theory was not correct, his influence is apparent in shaping Plato’s theory, and it helped to shift the mindset of other thinkers into realizing that fundamental change of substances is possible.

Because Plato’s theory does not recognize Anaximenes’s by name, some scholars have doubted that Plato’s theory was actually influenced by Anaximenes. The proponents of the influence have written that the uniqueness of Anaximenes’s theory and obvious similarities to Plato's theory prove the connection.[18] The opposing viewpoint attributes the similarities to mere coincidence. Because none of Anaximenes’s work exists today, there is controversy over the amount of influence Anaximenes’s had on Plato.

The Origin of the Cosmos

[edit]

Having concluded that everything in the world is composed of air, Anaximenes used his theory to devise a scheme that explains the origins and nature of the earth and the surrounding celestial bodies. Air felted to create the flat disk of the earth, which he said was table-like and behaved like a leaf floating on air. Anaximenes did not think that stars were floating leaf-like bodies similar to the earth and sun; instead, he thought of stars being similar to nails that are stuck in a transparent shell.[2] In keeping with the prevailing view of celestial bodies as balls of fire in the sky, Anaximenes proposed that the earth let out an exhalation of air that rarefied, ignited and became the stars. While the sun is similarly described as being aflame, it is not composed of rarefied air like the stars, but rather of earth like the moon; its burning comes not from its composition but rather from its rapid motion.[20] Similarly, he considered the moon and sun to be flat and floating on streams of air. In his theory, when the sun sets it does not pass under the earth, but is merely obscured by higher parts of the earth as it circles around and becomes more distant. Anaximenes likens the motion of the sun and the other celestial bodies around the earth to the way that a cap may be turned around the head.[21][22] Anaximenes believed that the sky was a dome, and day and night are caused by celestial bodies being carried North until they are no longer seen. There is evidence that suggests Anaximenes may have been the first person to distinguish between planets and fixed stars.[2]


Other phenomena

[edit]

Anaximenes used his observations and reasoning to provide causes for other natural phenomena on the earth as well. Earthquakes, he asserted, were the result either of lack of moisture, which causes the earth to break apart because of how parched it is, or of superabundance of water, which also causes cracks in the earth. In either case the earth becomes weakened by its cracks, so that hills collapse and cause earthquakes. Lightning is similarly caused by the violent separation of clouds by the wind, creating a bright, fire-like flash. Rainbows are the effect of sun rays on compacted air instead of the work of a goddess.[23] These examples show how Anaximenes, like the other Milesian philosophers, looked for the broader picture in nature. They sought unifying causes for diversely occurring events, rather than treating each one on a case-by-case basis, or attributing them to gods or to a personified nature.[24] This shows how Anaximenes helped in the transition of thought from mythology and religion to science.

Legacy

[edit]

The Anaximenes crater on the Moon is named in his honor.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Lindberg, David C. “The Greeks and the Cosmos.” The Beginnings of Western Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007. 28.
  2. ^ a b c d e f Dye, James (2014), "Anaximenes of Miletus", Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, Springer New York, pp. 74–75, doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-9917-7_49, ISBN 9781441999160, retrieved 2018-11-30
  3. ^ Great lives from history. The ancient world, prehistory-476 C.E. Salowey, Christina A., Magill, Frank N. (Frank Northen), 1907-1997. Pasadena, Calif.: Salem Press. 2004. ISBN 1587651521. OCLC 54082138.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  4. ^ a b "Anaximenes Of Miletus | Greek philosopher". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2018-11-30.
  5. ^ Kirk, G.S., J.E. Raven, and M. Schofield. "Anaximenes of Miletus." The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984. 143.
  6. ^ a b Guthrie, W.K.C. "The Milesians: Anaximenes." A History of Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962. 115.
  7. ^ a b c Vamvacas, Constantine J. (2009), "Anaximenes of Miletus (ca. 585–525 B.C.)", The Founders of Western Thought – The Presocratics, Springer Netherlands, pp. 45–51, doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-9791-1_6, ISBN 9781402097904, retrieved 2018-11-30
  8. ^ Lindberg, David C. "The Greeks and the Cosmos." The Beginnings of Western Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007. 29.
  9. ^ a b Mark, Joshua. "Anaximenes". Ancient History Encyclopedia. Retrieved 2018-11-18.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g Dye, James (2014), "Anaximenes of Miletus", Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, Springer New York, pp. 74–75, doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-9917-7_49, ISBN 9781441999160, retrieved 2018-11-30
  11. ^ a b c d e Vamvacas, Constantine J. (2009), "Anaximenes of Miletus (ca. 585–525 B.C.)", The Founders of Western Thought – The Presocratics, Springer Netherlands, pp. 45–51, doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-9791-1_6, ISBN 9781402097904, retrieved 2018-11-30
  12. ^ a b c "Anaximenes Of Miletus | Greek philosopher". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2018-11-30.
  13. ^ Guthrie, W.K.C. "The Milesians: Anaximenes." A History of Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962. 116.
  14. ^ Guthrie, W.K.C. "The Milesians: Anaximenes." A History of Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962. 124-126.
  15. ^ Kirk, G.S., J.E. Raven, and M. Schofield. "Anaximenes of Miletus." The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984. 146.
  16. ^ a b c d e Vamvacas, Constantine J. (2009), "Anaximenes of Miletus (ca. 585–525 B.C.)", The Founders of Western Thought – The Presocratics, Springer Netherlands, pp. 45–51, doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-9791-1_6, ISBN 9781402097904, retrieved 2018-11-30
  17. ^ Ancient Greece. Sienkewicz, Thomas J. Pasadena, Calif.: Salem Press. 2007. ISBN 9781587654121. OCLC 174134701.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: others (link)
  18. ^ a b c d Graham, Daniel W. (2015-12-30). "Plato and Anaximenes". Études platoniciennes (12). doi:10.4000/etudesplatoniciennes.706. ISSN 2275-1785.
  19. ^ Graham, D. (2003). "A testimony of Anaximenes in Plato". The Classical Quarterly. 53(2): 327–337.
  20. ^ Kirk, G.S., J.E. Raven, and M. Schofield. "Anaximenes of Miletus." The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984. 152-153.
  21. ^ Graham, Daniel W. "Anaximenes". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  22. ^ Fairbanks, Arthur. "Anaximenes[permanent dead link]". The First Philosophers of Greece. K. Paul, Trench, Trübner, 1898. 20.
  23. ^ Fairbanks, Arthur. "Anaximenes[permanent dead link]". The First Philosophers of Greece. K. Paul, Trench, Trübner, 1898. 18;20-21.
  24. ^ Lindberg, David C. "The Greeks and the Cosmos." The Beginnings of Western Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007. 29.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Barnes, Jonathan (1982). The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Routledge.
  • Burnet, John (1920). Early Greek Philosophy (3rd ed.). London: Black.
  • Freeman, Kathleen (1978). Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-03500-3.
  • Guthrie, W.K.C. (1962). The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hurwit, Jeffrey M. (1985). The Art and Culture of Early Greece, 1100-480 BC. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Kirk, G.S.; Raven, J.E. (1983). The Presocratic Philosophers (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Luchte, James (2011). Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn. London: Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-0567353313.
  • Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse, c. 600-450 BC. Vol. 3. London: Routledge.
  • Stokes, M. C. (1971). The One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies with Harvard University Press.
  • Sweeney, Leo (1972). Infinity in the Presocratics: A Bibliographical and Philosophical Study. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Taran, L. (1970). "Anaximenes of Miletus". Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. pp. 151–152. ISBN 0-684-10114-9.
  • Wright, M.R. (1995). Cosmology in Antiquity. London: Routledge.
[edit]


Category:6th-century BC Greek people Category:6th-century BC philosophers Category:Ancient Milesians Category:Philosophers of ancient Ionia Category:Presocratic philosophers