Jump to content

Talk:Majority winner criterion

Page contents not supported in other languages.
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Talk:Majority criterion)

Bad Wording

[edit]

In section 'Comparison with the Condorcet criterion' I see this wording: "The Condorcet criterion is stronger. According to it, a candidate X should win if for every other candidate Y there is a plurality of voters that answers affirmatively to the question 'Do you prefer X to Y?'." A plurality implies a win based on one choice receiving more votes than any other choice. Every majority is also a plurality. However, the term is normally used to refer to cases where the number of choices is greater than 2. The question 'Do you prefer X to Y?' is a yes or no question, so this wording leaves the reader scratching his head about what the other choices could be. I know that using the word 'majority' here would sound redundant, but something needs to be done, because the current wording is just too weird. --Comiscuous 2015-04-24 10:02 A.M GMT

What is the opposite?

[edit]

I can imagine an opposite criterion, that if a majority of voters prefer all other candidates to a given candidate, then the given candidate should not win. Which criterion is this (I'm sure it's in here somewhere!) ? This article should perhaps have a link to it?

Many would argue the majority criterion is something to explicitly *avoid*. Even Aristotle distinguished ochlocracy from democracy. A democracy is most definitely not tyrrany or the majority.

"This criterion is not accepted by all voting theorists"

[edit]

This is not a useful statement, as it applies to any criterion. If it were useful to be in an article, it should go on every criterion page, not just the criterion that is failed by User:Fahrenheit451's favorite voting method. RSpeer 14:59, Apr 25, 2005 (UTC)

User:Rspeer|RSpeer is back to false accusations and POV editing. It is a useful statement because it is true and I would agree that such statements should qualify voting method criteria. So we are not disagreeing on the truth of the statement, but rather if it is "useful" or not. --Fahrenheit451 15:04, 25 Apr 2005 (UTC)

You made such arguments on the Borda count page also. I respond that it is essential for information in Wikipedia to be useful, neutral, and true, and that truth is not a justification for including uninformative and misleading information.

From your point of view. I consider Not putting such a disclaimer in the definition to be uninformative and potentially misleading. --Fahrenheit451 21:44, 25 Apr 2005 (UTC)

It is highly suspect that the one criterion page you happened to include this statement on is the one failed by your favorite method, the Borda count.(Removed personal attack), while I am trying to put all well-known methods and criteria on equal footing. Can you guess what my favorite voting method is from my edits? RSpeer 18:58, Apr 25, 2005 (UTC)

I am begining to wonder if you are a suspicious person. I have been working to make all method articles accurate, relevant, and neutral. I don't know what "equal footing" means to you, but it is not Wikipedia criteria. From your antagonistic remarks, you favorite method is clearly not Borda count, plurality voting, or IRV. I would say the Schulze method is a, but not necessarily the, favorite of yours. Incidentally, Borda count is not my only favorite. --Fahrenheit451 21:44, 25 Apr 2005 (UTC)

The statement that you removed as a personal attack was not an attack on you, but on your contributions. For the same reason, I have not removed your allegation that my edits are POV.

Not bad on your guesses. Overall, I'd say my current favorite voting method is Approval, but I generally advocate using the right method for the right purpose. Schwartz Sequential Dropping (is that what you mean by Schulze?) is good for a crowd of geeks, like the Debian project, but too complicated in its statement for nearly any other purpose. And I think that Borda is pretty bad for elections, true, but actually pretty good for contests.

My other favorites are the Approval voting methods. These are easier for most folks to understand and deal with. e.i. There are some who are revolted at the thought of having to score all candidates on a ballot, even though they were nominated by their parties and should be given their due. CSSD is the same as the Schulze method. I think Borda works very well for elections with pre-screened candidates and honest voters. There aren't many political scenarios where those conditions are extant, so some variety of AV is the way to go. We certainly agree on the worst ones. --Fahrenheit451 22:25, 25 Apr 2005 (UTC)

I'm still not convinced that a statement that "This criterion is not accepted by all voting theorists" needs to go on every criterion page. What would it mean if a criterion were accepted by all voting theorists? That all voting theorists agreed that methods that failed that criterion were unworthy of being considered? I don't think a reader would be expecting there to be any such criterion.

I never was interested in going to war over that point.--Fahrenheit451 22:25, 25 Apr 2005 (UTC)

The Voting method page already states that no method can meet all the criteria. This statement should possibly be expanded, to explain that you (the implementor of a voting system) need to look at the criteria and decide which ones are important to the situation, when evaluating voting systems. But I am still against redundant text being placed on every criterion page, and especially against it only being placed on this page.

RSpeer 22:01, Apr 25, 2005 (UTC)

Bad English

[edit]

" The criterion states that if a majority of voters strictly prefers a given candidate to every other candidate and votes sincerely, then that candidate should win."

This sentence, taken from the article, is nonsense: (i) it is not the strictness of voters that is relevant, but the strictness of the majority; and (ii) how is the sincerity of voters intentions to be measured ?

A better sentence would be:

"The criterion states that if a strict majority of voters prefers a given candidate to every other candidate, then that candidate should win."

Thoughts ?--jrleighton 04:09, 6 January 2006 (UTC)

Once again, this wording comes from the electionmethods.org wording, where most criteria are defined in terms of sincere preferences.
(i) The term "strictly prefer" is used in case that "prefer" could be taken to mean "likes no less than."
(ii) Sincerity doesn't have to be measured. You set up a scenario and declare, "this faction is voting sincerely." Criteria aren't passed or failed based on actual elections.
KVenzke 00:04, 8 January 2006 (UTC)[reply]

Redundancy?

[edit]

What is the difference between Majority criterion and Condorcet criterion? Why are there separate articles for them?

The majority criterion only applies to first preferences: it says that an option should win if a majority has that option as their first choice. It is implied by Condorcet, because anyone who is the first choice of a majority necessarily beats every other candidate pairwise. rspeer / ɹəədsɹ 15:17, 21 April 2006 (UTC)[reply]
Thank you for clarification. I think that the wording of the article could be improved to emphasize the difference, but I feel I do not know the subject well enough to make the correction. When I read the article I thought that it meant pairwise comparisons.

Range Voting

[edit]

I notice that the change 02:01, December 23, 2006 by 71.252.99.34 added that range voting does not satisfy Majority criterion. There is a current issue as to the factuality of this on the range voting page. Does anyone have a citation to back up this claim? Thanks. WilliamKF 23:48, 12 March 2007 (UTC)[reply]

There are alternate wordings and interpretations of the Criterion. It's actually a mess. Depending on the exact wording, Range might or might not satisfy the Criterion. We might ask, what is the *intention* of this criterion? It is often conflated with "majority rule," but that's an error. Election methods in general produce conflicts with "majority rule," if by the latter, we mean how the majority would decide given full deliberative process. For starters, the latter is *at least* Condorcet compliant. But because it also incorporates the collection of preference strength information, it can consider far more than any ballot could indicate. Range probably comes closest to collecting the necessary information, but "majority rule" would require that the result not only be indicated by the method, but explicitly ratified by the majority. Election methods, in general, attempt to short-circuit the process in the name of efficiency.

Under the simplest interpretation of the Majority Criterion, which is reflected in the current definition as I write this, Approval satisfies the Criterion and Range does not. This is because Range allows the expression of preference strength, whereas the Criterion only looks at raw preference, a tiny preference is considered the same as a gotta-get-it-or-die preference. If you consider preference strength, you *must* violate the Majority Criterion, unless you use a trick like adding a ratification vote, in which case the criterion is satisfied by the overall process. In the end, the majority decides, perhaps, that it actually prefers a different candidate, one more widely acceptable. Abd 19:17, 16 May 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Non-rank ballots

[edit]

The previous wording of the criterion makes reference to "preferences" and "sincere voting" that are not valid elements of a voting criterion. Voting criterion should only refer to ballots and results. I added an alternate wording of the criterion (taken from one of the previously included external links, and referenced accordingly) that allows it to apply to non-rank methods. I also removed the example of Approval voting because it does not serve as a valid counter-example, given the corrected wording. I am reasonably sure that my changes are all factually correct, but am certainly open to being proven wrong here on the talk page. --Sapphic 19:47, 2 April 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Weaker than the Condorcet critereon?

[edit]

Um, majority is STRONGER than Condercet, not weaker. If a majority of all voters prefer A to *each* of the other candidates, then in a one on one with any candidate, he will be preferred, and win in FPTP.

This page is backwards.

--Michael —The preceding unsigned comment was added by 161.253.23.172 (talk) 01:42, 3 May 2007 (UTC).[reply]

I don't understand what you're saying. Majority is weaker than Condorcet. The way these criteria are usually understood, every method that satisfies Condorcet also satisfies Majority. KVenzke 23:22, 20 May 2007 (UTC)[reply]

I think the confusion is caused by the following: Both condorcet and majority criterions are implication sentences of the form "IF blah blah THEN X should win the election." In condorcet criterion the blah blah part is weaker than the blah blah part of the majority criterion. Hence the implication-form sentence that is the condorcet criterion is stronger than the implication-form sentence that is the majority criterion.

(This is a consequence of elementary logic: A->C is stronger than B->C if and only if A is weaker than B.)

Hence, if one thinks that the actual criterion is the blah blah part rather than the entire implication, then one thinks that the stronger-weaker should be reversed. (This kind of a person thinks that majority and condorcet are criteria for the victory of a given candidate, not criteria that a voting system may satisfy.) 128.214.51.113 (talk) 15:33, 27 April 2009 (UTC)[reply]

Maybe the article should be clarified so that we state that we talk about criteria that a voting system may satisfy rather than criteria that a candididate must satisfy in order to win? Can anyone formulate this clarification understandably?128.214.51.113 (talk) 16:17, 27 April 2009 (UTC)[reply]

The article is a bit unclear on one thing, and that unclarity is actually reflected in the ambiguity in the literature. The Majority criterion has an assumption incorporated in it that isn't stated, and the omission makes it ambiguous, and there is no consensus on how the criterion is to be interpreted, and no "voting system governing body" to determine what possible interpretation will prevail. The assumption is one of two. I'll state the simple version first.
A. If a majority of voters, with their votes, express a preference for one candidate over all others, that candidate wins.
Examples of methods which satisfy this criterion: Plurality, Approval Voting (!), Instant runoff voting, and any Condorcet method. (That's why the Concorcet Criterion is "stronger." Any Condorcet method satisfies the Majority criterion, but some methods which satisfy the Majority Criterion don't satisfy the Condorcet criterion, notable example, Plurality.)
Example of methods that fail: Borda, Range Voting. "Failure" doesn't mean that the method is "bad," or that "failure" is a defect; it's quite possible to argue that Range, for example, does better than satisfy the Majority Criterion.
B. If a majority of voters rank (mentally, internally, by some means other than voting) a candidate above all others, and vote any voting pattern consistent with this, but not necessarily expressing the preference, the candidate must win.
It's actually hard to express, which is why, ahem, I've argued that this shouldn't be the definition. But we don't get to define terms here, we can only report and use what's in the literature. Approval fails this second version because a voter may obviously prefer A to B, but votes for both of them, presumably because the voter prefers either of them to C. What is missing from the definition on our page is the assumption that the voter actually votes the preference (version A), or possibly does not vote the preference (version B). Given that voting methods don't read minds, there is no voting system which can use unexpressed preferences, but there are methods which might provide incentives to not express them. And the question rapidly gets very, very complicated.... --Abd (talk) 17:19, 27 April 2009 (UTC)[reply]

Standard Definition of Majority Criterion

[edit]

Wikipedia should reflect the near universal consensus for the definition, as it would appear in a text book, and not be distorted with a special exemption for Approval/Range, which was probably inserted to fulfill the POV of its advocates. The old existing citation (to Antioch) is to THIS corrected definition (my edit today) without the addition. The citation left the false impression that the source accepted the Approval-exempting re-definition. It does not. The citation lists Approval as NOT complying. It does have a footnote that offers some variants of how the Majority Criterion MIGHT be applied to non-ranked methods, but does NOT include the addition that I removed today.

The old link leads to this definition

"Majority criterion (MC): If more than half of the voters rank candidate X over every other candidate, then the winner should be candidate X.


Some methods that pass MC: Smith/minimax, sequential dropping, ranked pairs, beatpath, river, cardinal pairwise, minimax, plurality [*], IRV, two round runoff

Some methods that fail MC: approval [*], ratings summation, Borda"

Tbouricius 15:28, 9 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Tbouricius did not read the complete reference. I'll give him some time to do so before I respond in detail. In summary, Mr. Green-Armytage, the author of the reference, expresses his awareness that the definition of Majority Criterion, designed for ranked methods, is of problematic application to Approval Voting, so he attempts to come up with a definition designed for Approval and Range. Of course, this is altering the criterion to fit the method, and a strong suspicion must arise that the Criterion is being designed to fit some conception of pass or fail. I've seen numerous attempts to reword the Criterion to address the problem I have raised. And I specifically discussed this with Mr. Green-Armytage.
Tbouricius did not understand, apparently, the new definition. It was not designed to make Approval and Range *pass*, it was designed to make them *fail*. This shows that he is seeing all this through his political advocacy eyes. Approval satisfies the Criterion as written, the simple one. And, if not, then I suggest that how it fails be made explicit. Warning: there is a trick in the explanations I have seen, a sleight-of-hand over the meanings of "rank." It must have one very specific meaning if it is to make any sense. What does it mean to "rank" a candidate "over all others." Can you do this on an Approval Ballot? Can you do it on a Plurality Ballot? Can you do this on an IRV ballot? The answer is yes in all cases, I'll affirm. And in all cases, such a candidate must win the election. What in the world is the "consensus of the experts" talking about? I say that if we want to know expert opinion on this, we need to ask the experts. So I will. The mechanisms are in place, now, to do this fairly easily. It may take some time, though. Abd 06:25, 10 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
But Abd, the REASON I was suspicious of this non-standard addition to the ususal definition is that YOU referenced it as evidence that Approval Voting PASSED this criterion when you reversed my edit correcting this fact on the Approval article. Perhaps it was an accident, but when you undid my edit you not only restored the special case diefinition for cardinal systems, but also removed Approval Voting from the list of systems that fail it (although in this discussion you admit that it does. I will fix that, and let the non-standard definition stand with a caveat.
Tbouricius 14:55, 10 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
I didn't want to quibble, but the non-standard definition addition only applies to Range, not to Approval, as Approval doesn't use ratings. The cited source offers a different variant as a possible definition for approval and range...""If more than half of the voters prefer candidate X over every other candidate, and votes are sincere, then the winner should be candidate X." I would not object to someone replacing the text in the article with this, but I basically think the whole add-on should be removed as a non-standard definition.
Tbouricius 15:07, 10 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

(unindent)Well, if you want to quibble, you would be a *little* wrong.... Approval is a Range method with only two ratings, 0 and 1. However, I have taken out the suggested definition, because the Majority Criterion is broadly accepted and stated. Now, please take the trouble to describe how it is determined that Plurality satifies the criterion and Approval does not, not leaving out any steps. For example, saying that a voter "prefers" one candidate over another is useless if the voter does not actually mark a ballot accordingly. If you look at the Talk page above, you will see that the user who inserted the extended definition, User:Sapphos is not identifiable as a Range or Approval supporter... she was simply trying to be accurate, and she mentions specifically the problem that a voting method cannot mind-read the voter. So what does "rank" mean?

Is it a mental state or is it an action? Same with "prefer," as was used in some versions of the Majority Criterion, including one that was here earlier this year. To "prefer" can mean a mental condition or it can mean an action that selects. When applied to ranked methods, it clearly meant to mark the ballot to indicate preferences. Can the voter in Approval mark the ballot to indicate the preference involved in the Majority Criterion? There is one and only one way, which is to vote exclusively for that candidate. Otherwise the voter is not indicating an exclusive preference, rather the voter is indicating a *group preference*. So I have argued elsewhere, with some support and some opposition from election methods experts, that Approval (but not Range) satisfies the Majority Criterion. The "failure" of Range -- loaded language, that -- takes place because the voter, with Range, (i.e., add an extra rating or more to Approval) can express preference in a finer way, and this allows a minority candidate to win under certain circumstances -- which happen to be circumstances where it is arguable that the Majority Criterion is better being not satisfied.

What I've seen in arguments over this is that, in order to make Approval fail the Criterion, experts make the Criterion more and more complicated, tacking on clauses like, "Without impairing their ability to vote sincerely," and then when it is pointed out that there is no standard for "sincere voting" in Approval, i.e., all votes are sincere, practically by definition, if seen as indicating an approval cutoff, which can be set anywhere, they then must define "sincere vote" in a way which makes sense in Approval, and, in the end, it can all be seen as an attempt to avoid the basic problem: there is a subjective aspect to this criterion, *as conceived*. If we make it objective, taking it as stated, and interpreting "ranked" to mean something observable from the ballot, Approval passes, and a great deal of effort is wasted trying to make it otherwise.

Abd 04:50, 11 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

It is very simple and standard to apply the majority criterion to a variety of voting methods regardless of whether they use ranked ballots.
There is a claim made by Approval (and Range voting) advocates that the system is exempt from Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, and manages to side-step such tests as the Majority Criterion, because it is not a ranked voting method. I do not believe this assertion is supportable. For now let me limit my point to the Majority Criterion under discussion.
The majority criterion sets out a hypothetical scenario of voter preferences and then tests different voting methods in that unique scenario. The scenario imagined is one in which voters DO have clear preferences, and in this particular election a majority of voters consider one particular candidate to be the absolute best choice. This scenario exists PRIOR to deciding which voting method is to be used. The Majority Criterion test is simply; Is a given voting method certain to elect this candidate? If these voters in this scenario vote using certain methods (FPTP plurality, Condorcet, IRV, etc.) that particular candidate is certain to win, and thus they meet the majority criterion. If these voters vote using Approval (or Range, or Borda, etc.), that candidate may or may not win. Thus by definition, Approval fails the majority criterion.
One can argue whether the majority criterion is a good or useful criterion, but there really is no debate among political scientists about whether Approval fails this particular test. The fact that a particular voting method does not allow voters to express details about their full set of preferences, does not mean that voting system cannot be tested for a specific scenario, and cannot exempt it from the criterion.
I am restoring the definition of majority criterion to its more standard form, without the carve-out exemption of voting systems using unranked ballots.
Tbouricius 14:16, 18 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
You are absolutely correct that neither Approval or Range voting is exempt from Arrow's theorem. Approval is interesting in that it fails different parts of Arrow's criterion than Condorcet methods do, but that's another issue entirely.
As far as the 'ranked ballots' issue goes, that confusion is my fault- certainly something like Plurality voting passes the Majority criterion, even though it doesn't express complete preferences. Range Voting, on the other hand, can still fail the Majority Criterion even if no one expresses complete preferences on their ballot.
There are variations of approval voting that (clearly) pass the majority criterion, and my suspicion is that basic Approval Voting should not pass the criterion- After all, Approval voting is about voting in the most accepted candidate, not the most favored one. However, as several long debates on this page in others have demonstrated, whether Approval voting passes or fails depends heavily on the wording with which the majority criterion is defined. Even if approval voting is based on unexpressed preferences, and all voters vote sincerely, voters must also have incomplete information about each other's preferences in order for Approval voting to fail the Majority criterion. (If the majority favor a candidate and know it, they will always win in Approval voting). Paladinwannabe2 19:21, 22 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

Discussion of Majority Criterion opening on EMIG-Wikipedia

[edit]

Quite recently, the Election Methods Interest Group was organized, and it has so far attracted as members a few prominent election methods experts and at least one political scientist, and, knowing this community, I expect that we will see membership from many of the published writers and theorists in this field.

Membership in EMIG is open to all persons interested in the topic; however EMIG is developing a structure to address the noise problem in large-scale discussions. Cutting to the chase, EMIG can be thought of as a voluntary association of a series of individual "meetings." Each meeting is autonomous and self-defined. The goal is for all interested persons to register as members of EMIG at the top level (right now, that means subscribing to the EMIG mailing list), but that specific discussions are channeled to independent lists, virtual committees they might be called. EMIG has a delegable proxy mechanism in place, which allows, if used, all members to be represented in every discussion (ideally), without requiring personal and continual attention. So it is not time-expensive to belong to EMIG, you could join, look around, name a proxy you consider reasonably trustworthy, and then set your list membership to Special Notices. You would get hardly any traffic. Your proxy would let you know if something needs your personal attention.

So, if you are interested in editing articles on Election Methods, here on Wikipedia, other than simple grammatical and cleanup work, you may be interested in joining EMIG. There is a Wikipedia committee that has been formed, EMIG-Wikipedia, and a topic was opened there on the Majority Criterion, to attempt to settle, or at least explore in depth, differences of opinion that have appeared here. All are welcome to participate.

EMIG is not going to issue any controlling opinion, but if a Report is issued from the discussions of any EMIG committee, and if that report is accepted with the general agreement of a large body of election methods experts, reporting that consensus can be done by anyone, with clear implied authority, similar to a publication in a peer-reviewed journal.

Instead of having mere assertions about what "election experts believe," we can actually find out. Here are the links:

http://groups.yahoo.com/group/electionmethods/ is the top-level EMIG list and is where the proxy table is currently kept as well.

http://groups.yahoo.com/group/EMIG-Wikipedia is the Wikipedia committee.

Before posting to EMIG itself or a committee list, please consider reading the history of posts for EMIG as a whole and for the committee in question. —Preceding unsigned comment added by Abd (talkcontribs) 01:52, 13 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

How does the majority criterion apply to non-ranked methods?

[edit]

Tbouricius has edited the article back to use "prefer" instead of "rank," following arguments that discriminate between "prefer" and "rank." This is continuing a confusion of language that appears to go back to the original use of "majority criterion." It appears that the context was that of an expressed preference order allowed on the ballot, and it was assumed that the voter simply transferred an internal set of preferences to the ballot, "sincerely." There seems to be little difficulty defining "sincere" in this context, and any difficulties that remain seem, at least to me, to be irrelevant with respect to this criterion. It is enough, for this criterion, that if the voter has a preference for a single candidate over all others, that this candidate be ranked above all others, and on a complete preferential ballot, there is no difficulty doing this and the voting of the voter is not restricted.

The problem arises when a method does not allow complete ranking, and two examples of this would be Plurality and Approval. If we interpret the verbs "prefer" or "rank" to be literal actions, represented by marking a ballot, then Approval, we can readily see, passes the Majority Criterion.

If, however, we interpret those terms to refer to mental states devoid of action, but then translated into actual votes by some process called "sincere" in expanded definitions of the Criterion, it is arguable that Approval does not satisfy the Majority Criterion.

Bouricius maintained the citation in this article to the writing of James Armytage-Green, who clearly was, on the referenced page, struggling with the problem of defining "sincere voting," when it comes to Approval. He proposed a definition of "sincere" that, for him, resolved the question in favor of Approval failing. However, this was his own original research, as far as I can tell, (but it may be echoed elsewhere, or he may have gotten it elsewhere).

The question of how the Majority Criterion is defined is currently under discussion in the Election Methods Interest Group, but numerous questions remaining there have not been answered. No citations, for example, have yet been provided to primary sources for the exact wording of the Criterion. The question of how "sincere voting" is defined has not been addressed except by me.

These exact questions have previously been raised here, and the article came to be in a state where the interpretation that "prefer" refers to marks on the ballot was clearly the most accepted. Mr. Bouricius is a political scientist, we understand, and he often refers to an alleged consensus of "political scientists," but political scientists are not the only people who study and become expert regarding election methods. Further, the claim regarding a consensus of such has not been sourced. Is there any kind of review of the literature on this question, itself peer-reviewed, that addresses the problem? If there is, I'd love to see it!

I intend to add a section on the controversy over the Majority Criterion and its application to non-preferential methods. Otherwise this article is likely to oscillate, as new editors discover that the emperor has no clothes and act to fix the problem they perceive.

If the Majority Criterion is proposed as an objective method of comparing election methods, then it is crucial that every aspect of the Criterion be susceptible to objective application, or else we will have a subjective judgement being presented as if it were objective. Mr. James Armytage-Green, for example, does conclude that Approval Voting does fail the Criterion, but he has also acknowledged -- and it is plain from his cited page -- that he was looking for a way to define the Criterion so that Approval would fail, that being his intuition.

What he ended up with was pretty complex, and, in my opinion, failed to resolve the issue. His discussion is at the bottom of the cited page, [[1]] under the header: Note on criteria definitions for non-ranked methods. My comments are as follows:

I apply ranked ballot criteria to non-ranked methods as follows. 1. Change ranking-based wording to preference-based wording. For example, a criterion with the wording "a voter ranks A over B" is changed to "a voter prefers A to B". The wording "a voter ranks A equal to B" is changed to "a voter is indifferent between A and B".

Note that he clearly considers "rank" as different from "prefer." Both words, however, can refer to mental preferences or to actions, so simply changing the words is not enough. It must be explained.

2. Assume that votes are cast sincerely. In order to do this, I provide an operational definition of sincerity for plurality ballots and for approval ballots. 2a. Assume that a sincere vote on a plurality ballot entails voting for one's favorite candidate.

While that is reasonable, why is not the same assumption applied to all methods which allow that kind of expression? If we create separate versions of the Majority Criterion for each method we consider, we aren't applying an objective standard, for we can pick and choose between versions of the Criterion. My own opinion is that to resolve this issue, we are going to have to go back to roots. What is the most *useful* definition of the Majority Criterion? And it is not going to be easy to answer that question, I suspect. On the other hand, there *is* an approach which might succeed.

2b. Assume that an insincere vote on an approval ballot entails approving B but not approving A, if the voter prefers A to B, or is indifferent between A and B.

This is not a definition of "sincere," it is a definition of "insincere." Not all actions that are not insincere are therefore sincere. There is another definition of sincere vote: a vote that does not conceal a material preference. If the preference between A and B is "important," then, it could be argued, it is insincere to conceal it, and not concealing it, but revealing it, is sincere. A sincere vote must reveal what is material about the voter's preferences. I don't know how James came to think he had solved the problem with this assumption regarding an insincere vote.

Note: I am not entirely convinced by either of these definitions (in 2a or 2b), but they seem to serve our current purpose as well as anything else. Other applications are possible, and strictly speaking it's hard to argue that any single application is definitively correct. One approach is to ignore the possibility of unexpressed preferences and evaluate plurality and approval only with respect to expressed preferences. In that case, they pass just about anything you can think of, but this doesn't tell us very much, or capture the intent of the criteria themselves. Hence, I use the methods above for my tables.

Yet he never explicitly defined "sincere" vote! We know what is "insincere," and, indeed, there is no controversy over this. Would Armytage-Green want to put "not-insincere" in the definition? What if we do and we expand it?

If more than half of the voters prefer candidate X over every other candidate, and vote not insincerely, then the winner should be candidate X. "Not insincerely" means "not (reversing preference)".

It works for his intended effect, because a vote equating two candidates in the presence of some preference (even an infinitesimal one) is not a preference reversal and is therefore not insincere as he has defined it.

But is it "sincere?" Suppose there are only two candidates, and a voter has a preference between them, and votes to equate them (i.e., votes for both of them or votes against both of them). Is this a "sincere vote"?

Frankly, I don't think so. But why not? It is "not insincere," by the definition given by Armytage-Green. And not only does Approval fail by this "not-insincere" definition, so does Plurality.

To apply the majority criterion to non-ranked methods, it can be re-worded as follows: "If more than half of the voters prefer candidate X over every other candidate, and votes are sincere, then the winner should be candidate X."

Notice the sleight-of-hand. I know Mr. Armytage-Green, and I have utterly no suspicion of any dishonesty on his part (if he were dishonest, he would not have written so openly about his doubts), but somehow a definition of "insincere" was taken as adequate as a definition of "sincere."

The Majority Criterion is considered important because it seems intutitively related to the principle of majority rule. When Approval allegedly fails MC, it is because a majority has essentially voted Yes for two incompatible outcomes. There are two ways to resolve this, in democratic process, the presumption method and the deliberative method. The presumptive method assumes that, if more voters voted Yes for one option than the other, it is likely that a pairoff between the two would result in the election of the first option. It is an assumption which would usually be correct, and the presumptive option is law in several states that have referenda for multiple conflicting questions getting a majority. It saves a runoff. And the other option is to confirm the winner with further process, such as a runoff or even runoffs, as needed to gain a simple majority for one candidate over all remaining candidates. (There could be three candidates with a majority!). This would be what Robert's Rules prefers.

What seems clear to me is that Approval satisfies the *intention* of the Majority Criterion, even if it does not *technically* satisfy it under this difficult mental-preferences interpretation, so I'm not offended by the result of using only expressed preferences to analyze Criterion compliance. Yes, most actually-proposed election methods do satisfy the Majority Criterion, but not all, so it remains useful, within limits. For example, Range does not satisfy it, because Range allows expression of the necessary preferences, and it takes a more difficult definition of the Criterion to allow Range to pass. With Approval, it's the *simplest* interpretation.

Indeed, because raw Range Voting does not satisfy the Criterion, I would want to see a runoff triggered whenever ballot analysis in a Range election shows, as it would, that a winner was *not* the first preference of a majority, and, indeed, I'd make it stronger than that, I'd trigger it if there was any pairwise winner over the Range winner, making Range not only MC-compliant, but also Condorcet-compliant.

Basic question: what if many "political scientists" have written that Approval voting fails the criterion? Does this mean that we can ignore the Criterion itself and how it is applied, and simply rely upon, say, majority opinion among political scientists? If so, would we not need some measure or source for this? Is the statement of one political scientist, here, sufficient? Abd 18:15, 18 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

I'm trying to research the issue, and my best answer so far seems to be that the Majority Criterion does not apply to Approval voting (That is, it does not pass or fail the method). My second best answer is that it fails the Majority Criterion. Any reasonable wording of the Majority Criterion that causes Approval voting to pass also causes Plurality voting to pass as well. Keep in mind that if Approval voting does not pass the Majority Criterion, that's not necessarily a bad thing- it just means that someone acceptable to everyone is better than a candidate favored by 51% of the population. Paladinwannabe2 21:35, 18 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
The purpose of a Wikipedia article is to present scholarly consensus when it exists. When a small group of advocates dispute a schoplarly consensus, that MIGHT be worthy of mention, but the scholarly consensus should receive top billing and prominence. There is scholarly consensus about this issue. If someone can find a text book (not a Blog by an advocate) on election theory that says Approval is either not measurable against the Majority Criterion, or passes it, please let us know. I have NEVER found a legitimate source that disagrees with the statement that Approval fails the Majority Criterion. The only sourced link in the article on this states this as well.
Abd agrees that Range Voting fails the criterion. He also often states that Approval is merely a version of Range Voting (with limited scoring). This is further support for the general consensus among scholars that Approval (which Abd agrees is a subset of Range) does not pass.
Perhaps the problem is simply the name ... whcih implies majority rule. Maybe we just need to put that disclaimer in the introduction..."This criterion is one of many and does not mean a system assures or does not assure majority rule."
Plurality, which clearly can have non-majority winners and defeat majority rule, DOES pass the criterion, because the scenario presented in the test is so extreme. IF candidate A is preferred by an absolute majority of voters, and the voters express this preference to their best ability using the rules of the voting method in question (plurality), then A is certain to win. That makes it pass the Majority Criterion, as universally understood by election systems scholars. In the identical scenario (A preferred by a majority), but using Approval Voting, candidate A may win, or may not depending on how voters set their approval cutoffs for other possibly acceptable candidates. Since A is not CERTAIN to win, by definition Approval fails the criterion.
Tbouricius 20:33, 19 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
The problem I've been running into that the majority of sources I can find don't list Approval at all under the majority criterion, either as passing or failing (though they mention it elsewhere). You've given us 1 source to support Approval voting failing MC, and while I can find none that say it succeeds, that's still not enough evidence. Range voting obviously fails the majority criterion. This does not imply that Approval fails. Paladinwannabe2 20:50, 19 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
Voting criterion are useful only if we can apply them to ALL voting methods as a means of comparing. There is a simple, and rather standard definition for Majority Criterion that makes it meaningful and useful. "IF one candidate is preferred over all others by a majority of voters, does election method X assure the election of that candidate?" This definition obviously assumes voters express their sincere preference as best they can using the means available by method X. We don't need to debate what is a "sincere" vote with a situation of equal preference, because the test scenario sets out a situation where that is not the case. Unless one believes that the ONLY sincere vote under Approval voting was to vote exclusively for one's most preferred choice (and that is nonsense), then it fails the majority criterion, because the test situation is one in which voters have a range of preferences (and a nearly infinite number of possible cut-off points), but a majority distinctly prefer one particular candidate, and that candidate is not assured election.
It is obviously nonsense to debate whether the majority criterion should apply only to the marks on the ballot, rather than to the actual preferences of the voters. Imagine this hypothetical voting method...All ballots have one big box to mark that is so big that all candidate names fit against it. When the ballots are counted, any marks in the single box count towards the candidate who filed petitions for inclusion on the ballot first. So the marks become essentially meaningless. If we only consider the marks on the ballots, this candidate will win because he/she has a majority of non-blank ballots, without regard to the actual preferences of the voters. Arguing that this method passes the majority criterion (because we only look at the marks and the rules for counting them), or that the majority criterion does not "apply" to this method, defeats the entire purpose of having invented the criterion in the first place --- to compare voting methods. The criterion CAN be applied to this method. This foolish method would fail the criterion because the candidate ACTUALLY preferred by a majority of voters is not assured election.
Note that the "majority criterion" is not the only criterion dealing with majority issues (there is the mutual majority criterion, condorcet winner criterion and condorcet loser criterion, etc.)
As for additional references, they are uncommon because Approval Voting is a relatively recent name (recent re-invention in 1970s) while many others are centuries old. I know that The Mathematics of Voting and Elections: A Hands-On Approach by Jonathan Hodge and Richard Kilma deals with Approval Voting on pages 91-96. Rather than saying criterion do not apply (such as Arrow's five fairness criterion) they point out that Approval voting fails at least one of the five criterion (the universality criterion), and conclude that "Arrow's Theorem tells us that certain fairness criteria are incompatible with each other no matter what voting systems we consider." Unfortunately they do not discuss Approval specifically in terms of the majority criterion.
Tbouricius 19:05, 20 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]
One more point...If we all agree Range Voting fails the Majority Criterion, and that Approval is merely one specific subset of Range (with a score limited to 0 or 1), then why would we say the Criterion magically stops applying to this favored subset of a method that fails? The only reason is because someone wants Approval protected from getting a "bad rep." Approval advocates have pushed the myth that Arrow's Theorem does not apply to Approval for the same reason...miss-representing arrow's theorem as being limited to voting methods using ranked ballots (rather than to human communities with individuals with rankable preferences seeking to make a collective decision.)
Tbouricius 19:17, 20 October 2007 (UTC)[reply]

(unindent) I see that I did not respond to the last comments of Tbouricius; I will ignore the implied assertion of bad faith beyond mentioning it. The application of Arrow's theorem to "all methods" is controversial, and certainly Arrow did not make that claim. Rather, Arrow's theorem implies that any election method which satisfies a series of conditions cannot satisfy all of a certain series of criteria. Arrow's theorem is about the translation of a set of individual preferences, in rank order, to a single social preference order that satisfies the stated conditions. It's actually not about election methods, except that we may think of an election method as taking individual preferences and translating them into a *partial* social preference order, where we are only concerned about, say, a single winner. Arrow's theorem is proven, it is not controversial. If there is to be debate over the application of Arrow's theorem on Wikipedia, it should be in Talk for that article. The claim that Arrow's theorem does not apply to Approval is not at issue here, however, and Arrow's theorem is not an element in the arguments over whether or not Approval satisfies the Majority criterion. What I've been seeking -- and have not found, so far -- is a definition of the Majority criterion, reliably sourced, which can be objectively applied to all methods without making unstated assumptions. Thus, for example, notice that the article currently preserves the ambiguous wording of the criterion. Does "prefer" or "rank" refer to voter mental states or to an actual expression of preference or rank? If to the action, Plurality and Approval pass the Majority criterion. If to mental preference, then we must assume a certain correspondence between voter mental state and expressed vote, or *no* method passes the Majority criterion. (In particular, consider Plurality. A majority prefer one candidate, but are unaware that they are in the majority, and thinking that two other candidates are the frontrunners, prefer one of them and so vote. The majority preference fails to win. So it must be specified that the vote is "sincere." With ranked methods, that's easy. We require, for a vote to be sincere, that every rank be expressed, but, most notably, that the majority favorite be ranked ahead of all others, clearly that is a sincere vote, and any other vote is insincere, because it necessarily reverses rank. However, when ranks are truncated, and if equal ranking is allowed, it gets tricky.

This was all discussed above. Armytage-Green, as cited above, clearly is attempting to create a special definition of sincere vote that will cause Approval to fail, for he is aware that the standard definition causes it to pass! What he ends up with is a definition of an insincere vote: preference reversal, same as with ranked methods, and then he *assumes* that a vote that is not insincere is "sincere," and thus he can claim that Approval fails the criterion. Approval, however, does not ask the voters to vote for candidates, per se, but for a candidate *class*. Most voters will probably place only one candidate in that class, but they have the option of putting more in it. It is this additional freedom, not required by the method, which allows them to *conceal* their first preferencer. That concealment is not a sincere expression of the preference involved. But neither is it an insincere vote. (Oddly, critics of Approval will claim a tactical voting "vulnerability" for Approval, which requires defining a vote for more than one candidate as "insincere," or, alternatively, bullet voting in the presence of an asserted "sincere" approval -- which makes no sense as tactical voting, since the vote is for the preferred candidate of the two, i.e., is clearly sincere -- so critics, in that argument, claim that multiple approvals are "insincere." Yet, when the same critics assert Majority criterion failure, they are effectively calling the multiple approvals "sincere." Approval can't win for losing.)

In the ordinary meaning, Approval *always* rewards sincere voting; that is, the voter strategically has an incentive to vote for a set of candidates, each of which is preferred to every candidate in the not-preferred set. The *set* is sincerely and individually preferred to every non-member. Thus Approval is not vulnerable to tactical voting, period. However, that does not mean that there is no strategy, for there is no automatic boundary between the approved and non-approved sets. Strategy enters into the setting of that boundary; voters are advised, generally, to include in the Approved set, at least one frontrunner, and likewise, at least one frontrunner in the not-Approved set.

My *personal* opinion, though, is quite in line with Armytage-Green: Approval fails the Majority Criterion. (And, by the way, should be proud of it. The criterion is defective due to its total neglect of preference strength. And the problem with democratic principles only arises in very limited situations, of vanishingly rare negative consequence, and is avoided completely if there is a runoff whenever no candidate gains a clear and exclusive majority, quite in line with existing practice in many places. And this method -- Approval plus runoff -- *does* satisfy the Majority criterion.)

However, that opinion does not automatically give me a definition of the criterion. I did come up with one, I've proposed it, and nobody has written accepting it, as far as I recall, though formal process for peer-review hasn't begun. Essentially, it is the "not insincere" approach which merely formalizes what Armytage-Green found, with "insincere" meaning expressed preference reversal. In order to put this in the article, properly, it should be subjected to peer review and, if found acceptable, "published." That publication would not establish exclusive authority, but, given that the known reliable sources don't really address the situation, it might be effectively conclusive. --Abd (talk) 18:34, 27 December 2007 (UTC)[reply]

I see the following possibilities for defining the criterion in the context of absolutely-rated methods: (I'm not noting whether Plurality passes, because it always does.)
X must win if...:
1. ...a majority gives candidate X the maximum support, and does not give any other candidate Y the maximum support; Approval and MJ pass; Range does not.
2. ...a majority gives candidate X the maximum support, and prefers X over all others, and gives a non-insincere maximally-expressive vote: (Note that the "maximally expressive" part is necessary so that equal-ranking-allowed Condorcet methods do not suddenly fail this criterion) MJ passes; Approval and Range do not.
3. ...a majority does whatever it can to ensure that X will win. MJ, Approval, and Range all pass. Borda does not pass, because all potential opponents cannot be simultaneously buried. Still, the fact that Borda even comes close to passing makes this possibility seem impossibly wrong to me.
4. ...a majority prefers X over all others, and gives a non-insincere maximally-expressive vote: Neither MJ, Approval, nor Range pass (although 3-level medians with a Condorcet tiebreaker would.)
5. ...a majority expresses a preference for X over all others. Approval passes; MJ and Range do not.
6. ...it is possible to say, looking at the ballots, that any expressive honest majority preferred X to all others. Approval neither passes nor fails, the criterion simply doesn't apply; MJ and Range fail.
I think that 3 is pretty indefensible, so I won't say any more about it, except that it should probably be removed from the NB's on the voting system table. 6 is even worse.
Clearly, a pedant would choose 5; it is the most-direct extension of Arrow's verbal definition to rated systems.
Personally, I find definition 2 to be the most in line with the "spirit" of the criterion. However, I see that 1, 4, and 5 are all strictly simpler than 2, so I can't defend using 2 here without at least a reliable source. 4 is also unnecessarily complex, and moreover will have opposition from both Approval and MJ supporters. Therefore, I think that 5 and 1 are the best options. Of these two, I support 1, as being closest to what I feel the "spirit" of the criterion is. Verbally, it's more complex than 5; but mathematically, it's actually simpler.
If we're going to find some kind of compromise which "teaches the controversy", then I would support 1 and 4 as being defensible "poles of the debate". In this case, 5 is clearly dominated by 1, because I don't know anyone who really feels that 5 is the "right" definition; anyone who likes 5 will prefer 1. (That is, 5 is only possibly-viable as a pedantic compromise).
Actually, I think that "teaching the controversy" by including both 1 and 4 is the best solution. But probably explicit support for this position from reliable sources will be slim to none, so it's only viable if we have consensus (which also presumes nobody decides to be a pedantic #$@#$ to make a WP:POINT).
Homunq (talk) 12:08, 27 June 2011 (UTC)[reply]

Not objective

[edit]

...as explained in the third paragraph (and elsewhere):

The application of the majority criterion to methods which cannot provide a full ranking, such as Approval voting, is disputed.

79.69.36.210 (talk) 17:33, 8 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]

Clarification of meaning

[edit]

I've taken out two "examples" of majority voting, which didn't fit the definition.

With candidates XYZ with 39%,20%,41% first preference and 10%,80%,10% second preferences, 59% prefer Y to Z and 61% prefer Y to X ie a majority prefer Y to any other candidate (though a different majority). Under FPTP and IRV, Z would be elected, so do not meet this criterion as defined. Stephen B Streater (talk) 07:15, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]

It seems to me that you mixed up the majority criterion and the Condorcet criterion. Markus Schulze 09:47, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]
The criterion states that if there is a single candidate preferred by a majority of voters to all other candidates, then that candidate should win. In My case, candidate Y is preferred by a majority of voters to all other candidates. At least, I think the wording could be clarified (hence the title). Should it be: The criterion states that if there is a single candidate preferred by a majority of voters to all other candidates combined, then that candidate should win? Stephen B Streater (talk) 21:00, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]
I think you may be confusing majority with plurarity - see Majority: A majority, also known as a simple majority in the U.S., is a subset of a group consisting of more than half of the group. This should not be confused with a plurality, which is a subset having the largest number of parts. A plurality is not necessarily a majority, as the largest subset may be less than half of the entire group. Stephen B Streater (talk) 21:06, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]
In the case I gave above, Y is preferred by a majority to every other candidate, but would not be elected by FPTP or IRV, so this proves that (under the definition given) these do not meet the majority criterion. Stephen B Streater (talk) 21:06, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]
I've now changed the definition to match the cite - namely that the same majority has prefer the candidate - not just a majority. Stephen B Streater (talk) 21:14, 28 May 2010 (UTC)[reply]

Approval Voting Caveat and it's applicability to Range Voting

[edit]

There is a caveat at the bottom of the section on Approval voting, which illustrates with an example that candidate A with majority support can always be elected under Approval voting if his voters approve of him and only him on their ballots. This statement should be obvious: If there are N voters, and the majority supporting A votes this way, A will receive more than N/2 approval votes, and all other candidates must receive less than N/2 approval votes. In this sense, Approval satisfies the weaker claim that a candidate with majority support can always be elected via strategic voting on the part of his followers. This caveat is what leads to Approval's majority criterion status being listed as 'Ambiguous' on the Voting Systems Wikipedia page.

Range Voting satisfies exactly the same claim: If a majority of voters rank candidate A first, they can always force candidate A to win but giving A the maximum score allowable and all other candidates a score of 0 on their ballots. Yet, Range Voting's Maj. Crit. status is not listed as 'Ambiguous' on the Voting Systems page, and there was no such caveat for the example on this page until I added one in an edit.

That edit was swiftly deleted last month by Marcus Schulze, possibly due to a misunderstanding that I claimed Range satisfied the criterion. I have tried to make the wording more clear if that is the case. I would appreciate an explanation as to why it was deleted by him (or anyone else, if there is indeed something wrong in the statement).

66.131.184.130 (talk) 19:44, 26 September 2010 (UTC)[reply]

Please give a reference where the majority criterion is defined in this manner. Markus Schulze 00:13, 27 September 2010 (UTC)[reply]

I did not say this was a definition of the Majority Criterion, Mr. Schulze. In fact, I explicitly said the opposite above. I merely stated that the paragraph at the end of the section on Approval Voting applies equally well to Range Voting, and a similar argument should be included in that section, as well as a change made on the Voting Systems page to make the 'Ambiguous' status consistent. I don't see how one can be labelled ambiguous without the other. I guess it would make more sense to say on the voting system page that both Range and Approval unambiguously fail the Majority Criterion as it is defined here, but I will leave that to someone else.

If you feel the paragraph I included in the section on Range Voting unfairly implies that it satisfies the Majority Criterion, feel free to edit it in a way that makes the point more clearly. But it is true that under Approval and Range, if a majority supports a candidate, they can force that candidate to win by maxing out his score and minimizing his opponents' scores on their ballots, and I feel this is an important point to make. 66.131.184.130 (talk) 04:05, 28 September 2010 (UTC)[reply]

With the same justification, you could say that the Borda count satisfies the majority criterion. Markus Schulze 15:06, 8 October 2010 (UTC)[reply]
See the non-ranked section above. This caveat is based on what I've called definition 3 of the criterion. Although Schulze is technically incorrect (Borda does not satisfy the criterion under this definition), I think that his underlying point is valid: this is an indefensible argument. I've removed references to this line of argument from the voting systems table. Homunq (talk) 19:33, 28 June 2011 (UTC)[reply]

Approval & Majority - Is this source helpful?

[edit]

In Voting Matters Issue 6, (pertaining to “properties of preferential election rules”) Woodall: “…point-scoring systems and APPROVAL voting, fail majority.” http://www.votingmatters.org.uk/issue6/P4.HTM Filingpro (talk) 20:55, 11 August 2012 (UTC)[reply]

No, it's not at all helpful. Woodalls "majority" is NOT the "majority criterion" described in this article. In fact, Woodalls "majority" is called "Mutual majority criterion" in WP. Nevertheless, thanks for searching for reliable sources - this criterion could use some. --Arno Nymus (talk) 22:24, 11 August 2012 (UTC)[reply]
If Woodall applies Mutual Majority to Approval voting, then why wouldn't Majority also apply? Isn't it obvious to any editor in this field, that if approvals are regarded strictly equal preferences, then Approval can not possibly fail Mutual Majority? How can it? Woodall's mathematical model is a voter ordinal preference model, because he explicitly defines the mathematical model (in his terminology section) to be the ordinal preference listing of the voter.
To claim Majority does not apply to Approval, or Approval passes, or even to claim controversy, we must assume that voter approvals are equally preferred alternatives by the voter (or the voter's ordinal preference is removed from the mathematical model as irrelevant). The problem I see with this assumption (i.e. dichotomous preference model), is that Approval voting passes every criterion (except Unrestricted Domain) and is the perfect voting system, but of course it is not. It seems to me, an obvious reduction ad absurdum. I don't see the value of using this as a general model of Approval voting when comparing voting systems and how they perform with respect to criteria.
Filingpro (talk) 19:07, 26 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Citation For "Controversy" re: Approval??? How can we disregard voter's preferences?

[edit]

~Q: Can someone give a citation for the controversy section before I consider removing it?

~Q: I am failing to understand why any editor or theorist would advocate an interpretation of Majority that precludes the voter's preference? How can we possibly create a mathematical model of voting systems that preclude the voters themselves? What value could this possibly have, if we are not modeling the very subject matter at hand? Is it not axiomatic that voting systems are about choice amongst options by voters? How can we possibly not include in our model that voters have preferences amongst these options?

Approval experts tell us that if a voter prefers A>B>C then 'A' is a ballot marking and 'AB' are valid ballot markings.Filingpro (talk) 04:07, 22 May 2013 (UTC)[reply]

Does any theorist or any wiki editor think that Plurality should pass Majority? Of course not. (My apologies, Mutual Majority Filingpro (talk) 04:07, 22 May 2013 (UTC))[reply]

The idea of reinventing a definition of Majority to rely on whether a voter gives a candidate maximum support on a ballot, so that Approval can pass, disregards the voter's preferences form the model, because the approval cutoff decision is intrinsic to approval.

Filingpro (talk) 19:26, 19 May 2013 (UTC)[reply]

False claim re: strategic voting in IRV/Condorcet leading to failure of majority criterion?

[edit]

2nd paragraph in article, re: ordinal voting systems that pass the majority criterion (e.g. IRV, Condorcet etc.) may fail the majority criterion due to the voters incentive to "strategically rearrange their rankings"...

I am having difficulty coming up with an example.

I believe that if there is a majority that prefers candidate A first, then there is no strategic incentive for the majority to rank candidate A anything other than first. If they do so, there is no counter-strategy for the minority. Candidate A will always be elected and the majority criterion is always satisfied.

I will wait for comments before removing the paragraph.
Filingpro (talk) 16:43, 19 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Mischaracterization of "dispute" attributed to weighted preference ballots?

[edit]

3rd paragraph:

"The majority criterion was originally defined in relation to methods which rely only on voted preference orders of the candidates. Thus, its application to methods which give weight to preference strength is in some cases disputed."

Q: What does adding "weight" to preference strength have to do with difficulty in applying the majority criterion?

It seems to me, the reason for ambiguity, if at all, is the ability to give two candidates an equal rating on a rating ballot. When the voter does this using a limited rating ballot, it is ambiguous as to what the voter's ordinal preference might be: either >, <, or exactly equal =.

Q: How can we better describe what the "dispute" is and the reason for the dispute, if it exists at all?

Filingpro (talk) 17:05, 19 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Can we say Approval measures "strength" of preference?

[edit]

cardinal preferences (scale 0 - 100)
Voter X: A:49, B:51, C:100, approves BC (cutoff 50)
Voter Y: A:49, B:51, C:49, approves B (cutoff 50)

B wins

But Y weakly prefers B to C (2 point differential), while X strongly prefers C to B (49 point differential)

If approval measures strength of preference, why doesn't C win?

Note that Y is more or less indifferent to the options, but X has a strong preference for C.

Filingpro (talk) 19:47, 26 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

Why is the assumption of perfect information and strategic voting mentioned in the section for Approval's failure/passage of Majority?

[edit]

"In the strict sense, where a majority of voters consider one candidate better than all others, Approval voting empowers those voters to elect their favorite candidate, but it does not force them to. Voters in a majority bloc can bullet vote to guarantee their top choice is elected. However, if some of those voters prefer to seek a consensus candidate with broader support, Approval voting allows them to do so."

Doesn't every voting method empower voters to elect the majority candidate or a consensus candidate, having perfect information about other voters?

Why does this comment belong in this section?

I believe the whole point of the failure of the Majority criterion is that Approval voting may do so against the voter's will, not when they have perfect information to vote strategically.

I motion to remove this, but I am open to saying something positive about Approval in another section, or here if it can be clarified what is the intent and purpose here and how it is relevant.
Filingpro (talk) 08:11, 27 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

What is the basis for the definition of Majority under which Approval passes?

[edit]

The article argues that Approval voting passes or fails Majority, depending on the definition of the criterion.

"If "prefer" includes an actual expression of the preference ("giving it a better vote"), then Approval voting satisfies the majority criterion. On the other hand, if "prefer" does not include an actual expression of the preference on the ballot ("don't vote it worse"), then Approval voting fails the criterion as shown by the subsequent example."

There are several problems I see:

(1) It characterizes one side of the debate (I believe the correct side) incorrectly. It says "prefer" does not include an actual expression of the preference on the ballot (for Approval to fail). That is incorrect. It may or may not. Those of us who argue Approval fails the Majority criterion, point out that the definition of the criterion refers to the voter's preferences. The debate over the Approval ballot is a red herring, because the criterion uses a voter ordinal preference model (as conceded by the article itself).

(2) The other problem with the position that we should interpret Majority criterion to be referring to literal markings on an Approval ballot (rather than voter ordinal preferences as the criterion is defined), is that this assumption leads to absurd results that I can not fathom how any editor in the field can ignore. That is, if you take only the markings on the Approval ballot when considering criteria compliance, Approval voting passes every criterion and is the perfect voting system, which it is obviously not. It is obvious that when a majority of voters prefer a particular candidate above all others, Approval does not necessarily elect this candidate, simply because voters in the majority might also approve a compromise candidate. I fear we have made this article far too complicated, based on what seems to me to be logically absurd, indefensible WP:OR.

(3) The rhetorical approach I am also concerned is misleading. The paragraph states Approval passes as long as we "include actual expression of preferences" and it fails if we "do not include actual expression of preferences". The implication is that the way we make Approval fail is to not include actual stuff, but it passes when we include actual stuff. The truth: Approval passes only when we do not include voter preferences. It fails when we include voter preferences. Ironically, it is the Approval voting system itself that fails to include the articulation of voters actual preferences. Adding to irony, it is claimed that the limited ratings (0, 1) are "actual preferences." Of whom? For Approval to pass, requires the removal of (i.e. do not "include") the voter from the mathematical model.

Filingpro (talk) 10:09, 27 July 2014 (UTC)[reply]

[edit]

Hello fellow Wikipedians,

I have just modified one external link on Majority criterion. Please take a moment to review my edit. If you have any questions, or need the bot to ignore the links, or the page altogether, please visit this simple FaQ for additional information. I made the following changes:

When you have finished reviewing my changes, you may follow the instructions on the template below to fix any issues with the URLs.

This message was posted before February 2018. After February 2018, "External links modified" talk page sections are no longer generated or monitored by InternetArchiveBot. No special action is required regarding these talk page notices, other than regular verification using the archive tool instructions below. Editors have permission to delete these "External links modified" talk page sections if they want to de-clutter talk pages, but see the RfC before doing mass systematic removals. This message is updated dynamically through the template {{source check}} (last update: 5 June 2024).

  • If you have discovered URLs which were erroneously considered dead by the bot, you can report them with this tool.
  • If you found an error with any archives or the URLs themselves, you can fix them with this tool.

Cheers.—InternetArchiveBot (Report bug) 16:17, 13 January 2018 (UTC)[reply]

Requested move 21 May 2024

[edit]
The following is a closed discussion of a requested move. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made in a new section on the talk page. Editors desiring to contest the closing decision should consider a move review after discussing it on the closer's talk page. No further edits should be made to this discussion.

The result of the move request was: no consensus. The proposed titles were both identified as possibly confusing, as other types of criteria are sometimes called the "majority criterion" or "majority winner criterion", but the existing title was also identified as uncommon. There was little back-and-forth discussion, which meant that no title was able to gain consensus as clearly preferable to the others. (closed by non-admin page mover) ModernDayTrilobite (talkcontribs) 15:37, 14 June 2024 (UTC)[reply]


Majority favorite criterionmajority criterion – To stay consistent with the names at Wikipedia, I recommend that this page should be moved to "majority criterion" or "majority winner criterion". There are already the Condorcet winner criterion, the Condorcet loser criterion, and the majority loser criterion. Who uses the term "majority favorite criterion" anyway? Markus Schulze 18:00, 21 May 2024 (UTC) — Relisting. BilledMammal (talk) 04:00, 29 May 2024 (UTC) — Relisting. BilledMammal (talk) 07:49, 6 June 2024 (UTC)[reply]

'majority winner criterion' is more consistent no?—blindlynx 18:57, 21 May 2024 (UTC)[reply]
@MarkusSchulze "Majority winner criterion" is a definite no-go because that already has a completely different meaning, as another term for the Condorcet winner criterion (as Condorcet winners are often called majority winners in the welfare economics literature).
Notably, this is why I renamed the article: I've seen "Majority criterion" being used to refer to the mutual majority criterion, Condorcet winner criterion, and then (by Woodall) for this criterion. From what I can tell, prior to Woodall's attempt at redefining the term, the most common use was to refer to Condorcet's majority criterion.
In theory this could be called something like Woodall's majority criterion, I suppose. I don't think any of these terms is very consistently used. The EM list seems to have eventually settled on calling this the majority criterion, but I don't think this is a standard use outside of it. –Sincerely, A Lime 01:36, 22 May 2024 (UTC)[reply]
The discussion above is closed. Please do not modify it. Subsequent comments should be made on the appropriate discussion page. No further edits should be made to this discussion.