Jump to content

Radical probabilism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Radical probabilism is a hypothesis in philosophy, in particular epistemology, and probability theory that holds that no facts are known for certain. That view holds profound implications for statistical inference. The philosophy is particularly associated with Richard Jeffrey who wittily characterised it with the dictum "It's probabilities all the way down."

Background

[edit]

Bayes' theorem states a rule for updating a probability conditioned on other information. In 1967, Ian Hacking argued that in a static form, Bayes' theorem only connects probabilities that are held simultaneously; it does not tell the learner how to update probabilities when new evidence becomes available over time, contrary to what contemporary Bayesians suggested.[1]

According to Hacking, adopting Bayes' theorem is a temptation. Suppose that a learner forms probabilities Pold(A & B) = p and Pold(B) = q. If the learner subsequently learns that B is true, nothing in the axioms of probability or the results derived therefrom tells him how to behave. He might be tempted to adopt Bayes' theorem by analogy and set his Pnew(A) = Pold(A | B) = p/q.

In fact, that step, Bayes' rule of updating, can be justified, as necessary and sufficient, through a dynamic Dutch book argument that is additional to the arguments used to justify the probability axioms. This argument was first put forward by David Lewis in the 1970s though he never published it.[2] The dynamic Dutch book argument for Bayesian updating has been criticised by Hacking,[1] Kyburg,[3] Christensen,[4] and Maher.[5][6] It was defended by Brian Skyrms.[2]

Certain and uncertain knowledge

[edit]

That works when the new data is certain. C. I. Lewis had argued that "If anything is to be probable then something must be certain".[7] There must, on Lewis' account, be some certain facts on which probabilities were conditioned. However, the principle known as Cromwell's rule declares that nothing, apart from a logical law, if that, can ever be known for certain. Jeffrey famously rejected Lewis' dictum.[8] He later quipped, "It's probabilities all the way down," a reference to the "turtles all the way down" metaphor for the infinite regress problem. He called this position radical probabilism.[9]

Conditioning on an uncertainty – probability kinematics

[edit]

In this case Bayes' rule isn't able to capture a mere subjective change in the probability of some critical fact. The new evidence may not have been anticipated or even be capable of being articulated after the event. It seems reasonable, as a starting position, to adopt the law of total probability and extend it to updating in much the same way as was Bayes' theorem.[10]

Pnew(A) = Pold(A | B)Pnew(B) + Pold(A | not-B)Pnew(not-B)

Adopting such a rule is sufficient to avoid a Dutch book but not necessary.[2] Jeffrey advocated this as a rule of updating under radical probabilism and called it probability kinematics. Others have named it Jeffrey conditioning.

Alternatives to probability kinematics

[edit]

Probability kinematics is not the only sufficient updating rule for radical probabilism. Others have been advocated including E. T. Jaynes' maximum entropy principle, and Skyrms' principle of reflection. It turns out that probability kinematics is a special case of maximum entropy inference. However, maximum entropy is not a generalisation of all such sufficient updating rules.[11]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Hacking, Ian (1967). "Slightly more realistic personal probability". Philosophy of Science. 34 (4): 311–325. doi:10.1086/288169. S2CID 14344339.
  2. ^ a b c Skyrms, Brian (1987a). "Dynamic coherence and probability kinematics". Philosophy of Science. 54: 1–20. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.395.5723. doi:10.1086/289350. S2CID 120881078.
  3. ^ Kyburg, H. (1978). "Subjective probability: Criticisms, reflections and problems". Journal of Philosophical Logic. 7: 157–180. doi:10.1007/bf00245926. S2CID 36972950.
  4. ^ Christensen, D. (1991). "Clever bookies and coherent beliefs". Philosophical Review. 100 (2): 229–47. doi:10.2307/2185301. JSTOR 2185301.
  5. ^ Maher, P (1992a). Betting on Theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  6. ^ Maher, Patrick (1992b). "Diachronic rationality". Philosophy of Science. 59: 120–41. doi:10.1086/289657. S2CID 224830300.
  7. ^ Lewis, C. I. (1946). An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court. p. 186.
  8. ^ Jeffrey, Richard C. (2004). "Chapter 3". Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  9. ^ Skyrms, B (1996). "The structure of radical probabilism". Erkenntnis. 45 (2–3): 285–97. doi:10.1007/BF00276795.
  10. ^ Jeffrey, Richard (1987). "Alias Smith and Jones: The testimony of the senses". Erkenntnis. 26 (3): 391–399. doi:10.1007/bf00167725. S2CID 121478331.
  11. ^ Skyrms, B (1987b). "Updating, supposing and MAXENT". Theory and Decision. 22 (3): 225–46. doi:10.1007/bf00134086. S2CID 121847242.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Jeffrey, R (1990) The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-39582-0
  • — (1992) Probability and the Art of Judgment. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-39770-7
  • — (2004) Subjective Probability: The Real Thing. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-53668-5
  • Skyrms, B (2012) From Zeno to Arbitrage: Essays on Quantity, Coherence & Induction. Oxford University Press (Features most of the papers cited below.)
[edit]