Experimental jurisprudence
Experimental jurisprudence (X-Jur) is an emerging field of legal scholarship that explores the nature of legal phenomena through psychological investigations of legal concepts.[1][2][3][4] The field departs from traditional analytic legal philosophy in its ambition to elucidate common intuitions in a systematic fashion employing the methods of social science. Equally, unlike research in legal psychology, X-Jur emphasises the philosophical implications of its findings, such as whether, how, and in what respects the law's content is a matter of moral perspective. Whereas some legal theorists have welcomed X-Jur's emergence, others have expressed reservations about the contributions it seeks to make.
Background
[edit]Experimental jurisprudence (X-Jur) is an outgrowth of the broader experimental philosophy (X-Phi) movement. Emerging in the early 2000s, and focusing initially on the folk concepts of semantic reference, knowledge, and intentional action, X-Phi represented a rejection of analytic philosophy's traditional 'armchair' speculation about common conceptual intuitions.[5] As a similarly empirical approach to the analysis of folk legal concepts developed in the 2010s, the prospect of a novel method of legal theory, 'experimental jurisprudence', was recognised.[6]
X-Jur shares analytic philosophy's interest in a range of questions, including the longstanding issue of whether the existence and content of the law is a matter of social fact alone.[7] But X-Jur scholarship has argued that philosophers' appeals to the content of folk legal concepts[8][9] ought to be tested empirically so that, the 'big [philosophical] cost of rely[ing]... on… a concept that is distinct from that used by folk',[10] may be allocated correctly.[11][12]
Themes
[edit]X-Jur exhibits two basic lines of inquiry into, respectively, the folk concepts associated with features of particular laws or legal methods that are common among modern legal systems, and the general folk concepts of law and of rule application or legal interpretation.
Specific legal concepts
[edit]One broad X-Jur research agenda concerns topics in 'special' jurisprudence. Legal theory often attributes the conceptual elements of common legal rules to particular ethical theories or to certain descriptive (non-moralistic) sorts of judgment. X-Jur has challenged many of these traditional theoretical understandings. For instance:
- It has been argued that empirical data about people's ordinary causal judgements supports a model of legal causation that, contrary to legal doctrine, is not purely descriptive in nature but which features a role for moral judgements about norms.[13]
- Studies on professional judges' ascriptions of criminal intent (mens rea) have been reported that suggest that, just like folk ascriptions, judicial ascriptions of intentional action (guilt) are affected by the moral valence of the consequences of the acts in question.[14]
- Ordinary people have been found to focus on the conditions that are perceived to be essential to consent and so may not consider an individual's consent (to sex, for example) to be nullified by the violation of a condition that the individual herself considers to be a prerequisite. This result has been taken to explain courts' failure, in variety of contexts, to apply the autonomy-based model of consent to which many ethical theories subscribe.[15]
- Many legal theorists and judges argue that statutes (and constitutions) should be construed according to their 'ordinary meaning', as determined by dictionaries or corpus linguistics.[16] Studies have been reported that suggest that ordinary people's ascriptions of linguistic meaning may diverge from both these sources.[17]
Collectively, this line of research suggests that a priori assumptions about the relationship between legal doctrine and associated folk legal concepts call for philosophically informed empirical investigation.[1]
General concept of law
[edit]A narrower X-Jur research agenda concerns topics in 'general' jurisprudence, namely, the questions of the nature of law itself and of the application or interpretation of rules in general. This research has reported that, in contrast to traditional accounts of legal meaning, which reduce it to a single dimension, either the rule maker's intention[18] or the rule's text,[19] a range of factors are intuitively at work in the application of rules.[20][21][22] Indeed, recent studies suggest that, in line with moralistic accounts of legal interpretation,[23] rule violation judgments may sometimes be influenced by moral appraisals.[24][25]
The question of whether morality is a prerequisite of legal validity has also attracted empirical scrutiny, with studies exploring both whether the folk concept of law includes Lon Fuller's principles of procedural morality[26] and/or substantive moral principles, such as basic gender and racial equality. Such scholarship suggests that the satisfaction of procedural moral principles is not intuitively critical to legal validity, at least when considering specific statutes.[11] In contrast, consistently with natural law theory, these studies indicate that a statute's substantive morality is intuitively intrinsic to its existence as law.[12]
Together, these lines of research have challenged the consistency with ordinary language of legal positivism, the view that the law's representation of moral values is ultimately just a matter of political circumstance.[3]
Criticism
[edit]X-Jur's commitment to the potential philosophical significance of systematic research into folk concepts has been welcomed by some legal theorists[27] but has also attracted criticism.[28] According to one line of objection, treating folk concepts as a basis for legal philosophy is liable to reduce such inquiry to a 'glorified lexicography' whose results will be culturally contingent, and which will be unable to point to universal and timeless truths.[29] The range of cross-cultural or nationally representative X-Jur remains limited; there are indications, however, that at least some features of folk legal concepts, notably the role of procedural morality, may be found in both culturally and linguistically diverse locations.[30]
A second line of objection focuses on X-Jur that documents laypeople's intuitions. It claims that, for philosophical purposes, the understandings of law and legal concepts that matter are not those of the population at large but rather those of lawyers and legal officials.[31] Analogously to criticism of X-Phi that privileges the 'expert' intuitions of philosophers over those laypeople,[32] this view holds that the shared emphasis on folk legal concepts of both analytic and experimental approaches overlooks the importance of training and expertise in the construction and maintenance of both legal systems and of discrete legal phenomena.
References
[edit]- ^ a b Tobia, Kevin (2022). "Experimental Jurisprudence". University of Chicago Law Review. 89 (3): 735.
- ^ Sommers, Roseanna (2021). "Experimental jurisprudence". Science. 373 (6553): 394–395. doi:10.1126/science.abf0711. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 34437107. S2CID 236179587.
- ^ a b Prochownik, Karolina Magdalena (2021). "The experimental philosophy of law: New ways, old questions, and how not to get lost". Philosophy Compass. 16 (12). doi:10.1111/phc3.12791. ISSN 1747-9991. S2CID 244057904.
- ^ Flanagan, Brian. "The Burning Armchair: Can Jurisprudence be Advanced by Experiment?". SSRN 4624493.
- ^ Knobe, Joshua (2007). "Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Significance". Philosophical Explorations. 10 (2): 119–121. doi:10.1080/13869790701305905. ISSN 1386-9795. S2CID 171040750.
- ^ Solum, Lawrence (2014). "The Positive Foundations of Formalism: False Necessity and American Legal Realism". Harvard Law Review. 127: 2464.
- ^ Raz, Joseph (2013). Ethics in the Public Domain: essays in the morality of law and politics. Oxford University Press. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-19-825837-7. OCLC 880544173.
- ^ Raz, Joseph (2002). Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-826834-3. OCLC 290617123.
- ^ Finnis, John (2020), "Natural Law Theories", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-09-05
- ^ Plunkett, David (2012). "A Positivist Route for Explaining How Facts Make Law". Legal Theory. 18 (2): 204. doi:10.1017/s1352325212000079. ISSN 1352-3252. S2CID 143438667.
- ^ a b Donelson, Raff; Hannikainen, Ivar R. (2020). "Fuller and the Folk". Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy. Vol. 3. Oxford University Press. pp. 6–28. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198852407.003.0002. ISBN 978-0-19-885240-7.
- ^ a b Flanagan, Brian; Hannikainen, Ivar R. (2020). "The Folk Concept of Law: Law Is Intrinsically Moral". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 100 (1): 165–179. doi:10.1080/00048402.2020.1833953. ISSN 0004-8402. S2CID 228861665.
- ^ Knobe, Joshua; Shapiro, Scott (2021). "Proximate Cause Explained: An Essay in Experimental Jurisprudence". University of Chicago Law Review. 88 (1). ISSN 0041-9494.
- ^ Kneer, Markus; Bourgeois-Gironde, Sacha (2017). "Mens rea ascription, expertise and outcome effects: Professional judges surveyed". Cognition. 169: 139–146. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2017.08.008. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 28889031. S2CID 46741256.
- ^ Sommers, Roseanna (2020). "Commonsense Consent" (PDF). Yale Law Journal. 129: 2232.
- ^ Scalia, Antonin (1997). A matter of interpretation : federal courts and the law: an essay. Amy Gutmann. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-02630-0. OCLC 35280772.
- ^ Tobia, Kevin (2020). "Testing Ordinary Meaning". Harvard Law Review. 134: 726.
- ^ Alexander, Larry; Sherwin, Emily (2008). Demystifying Legal Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/cbo9781139167420. ISBN 978-0-521-87898-2.
- ^ Schauer, Frederick (2016). "Institutions and the Concept of Law: A Reply to Ronald Dworkin (with some help from Neil MacCormick)". In Bankowski, Zenon (ed.). Law as Institutional Normative Order. doi:10.4324/9781315591544. ISBN 978-1-317-10771-2.
- ^ Struchiner, Noel; Hannikainen, Ivar; Almeida, Guilherme (2020). "An experimental guide to vehicles in the park" (PDF). Judgment and Decision Making. 15 (3): 312–29. doi:10.1017/S1930297500007130. S2CID 215796900.
- ^ Bregant, Jessica; Wellbery, Isabel; Shaw, Alex (2019). "Crime but not punishment? Children are more lenient toward rule-breaking when the "spirit of the law" is unbroken". Journal of Experimental Child Psychology. 178: 266–282. doi:10.1016/j.jecp.2018.09.019. ISSN 0022-0965. PMID 30415148. S2CID 53292715.
- ^ Turri, John; Blouw, Peter (2014). "Excuse Validation: a study in rule-breaking". Philosophical Studies. 172 (3): 615–634. doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0322-z. ISSN 0031-8116. S2CID 254946036.
- ^ Dworkin, Ronald (1986). Law's Empire. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press. ISBN 0-674-51835-7. OCLC 12945691.
- ^ LaCosse, Jennifer; Quintanilla, Victor (2021). "Empathy influences the interpretation of whether others have violated everyday indeterminate rules". Law and Human Behavior. 45 (4): 287–309. doi:10.1037/lhb0000456. ISSN 1573-661X.
- ^ Flanagan, Brian; de Almeida, Guilherme F. C. F.; Struchiner, Noel; Hannikainen, Ivar (2023). "Moral Appraisals Guide Intuitive Legal Determinations". Law and Human Behavior. 47 (2): 367–383. doi:10.1037/lhb0000527. PMID 37053387. S2CID 245528891.
- ^ Fuller, Lon L. (2006). The Morality of Law. Legal Classics Library. OCLC 271216569.
- ^ Atiq, Emad (2022). "Disagreement about Law and Morality: Empirical Results and the Meta-Problem of Jurisprudence". Jotwell. Retrieved 2022-09-13.
- ^ Himma, Kenneth Einar (2023). "Replacement naturalism and the limits of experimental jurisprudence". Jurisprudence. 14 (3): 348–373. doi:10.1080/20403313.2023.2208002. ISSN 2040-3313. S2CID 258875256.
- ^ Leiter, Brian (2017). "Beyond the Hart/Dworkin Debate: The Methodology Problem in Jurisprudence". The Methodology of Legal Theory. Routledge. pp. 241–275. doi:10.4324/9781315085944-11. ISBN 978-1-315-08594-4.
- ^ Hannikainen, Ivar R.; Tobia, Kevin P.; Almeida, Guilherme da F. C. F.; Donelson, Raff; Dranseika, Vilius; Kneer, Markus; Strohmaier, Niek; Bystranowski, Piotr; Dolinina, Kristina; Janik, Bartosz; Keo, Sothie; Lauraitytė, Eglė; Liefgreen, Alice; Próchnicki, Maciej; Rosas, Alejandro (2021). "Are There Cross-Cultural Legal Principles? Modal Reasoning Uncovers Procedural Constraints on Law". Cognitive Science. 45 (8): e13024. doi:10.1111/cogs.13024. hdl:10481/70654. ISSN 0364-0213. PMID 34379347. S2CID 236777491.
- ^ Jiménez, Felipe (2021). "Some Doubts About Folk Jurisprudence: The Case of Proximate Cause". The University of Chicago Law Review Online.
- ^ Devitt, Michael (2010). "Experimental Semantics". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 82 (2): 418–435. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00413.x. ISSN 0031-8205.