Jump to content

Multi-issue voting

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Perpetual voting)

Multi-issue voting is a setting in which several issues have to be decided by voting. Multi-issue voting raises several considerations, that are not relevant in single-issue voting.

The first consideration is attaining fairness both for the majority and for minorities. To illustrate, consider a group of friends who decide each evening whether to go to a movie or a restaurant. Suppose that 60% of the friends prefer movies and 40% prefer restaurants. In a one-time vote, the group will probably accept the majority preference and go to a movie. However, making the same decision again and again each day is unfair, since it satisfies 60% of the friends 100% of the time, while the other 40% are never satisfied. Considering this problem as multi-issue voting allows attain a fair sequence of decisions by going 60% of the evenings to a movie and 40% of the evenings to a restaurant. The study of fair multi-issue voting mechanisms is sometimes called fair public decision making.[1] The special case in which the different issues are decisions in different time-periods, and the number of time-periods is not known in advance, is called perpetual voting.[2][3][4]

The second consideration is the potential dependence between the different issues. For example, suppose the issues are two suggestions for funding public projects. A voter may support funding each project on its own, but object to funding both projects simultaneously, due to its negative influence on the city budget. If there are only few issues, it is possible to ask each voter to rank all possible combinations of candidates. However, the number of combinations increases exponentially in the number of issues, so it is not practical when there are many issues. The study of this setting is sometimes called combinatorial voting.[5]

Definitions

[edit]

There are several issues to be decided on. For each issue t, there is a set Ct of candidates or alternatives to choose from. For each issue t, a single candidate from Ct should be elected. Voters may have different preferences regarding the candidates. The preferences can be numeric (cardinal ballots) or ranked (ordinal ballots) or binary (approval ballots). In combinatorial settings, voters may have preferences over combinations of candidates.

A multi-issue voting rule is a rule that takes the voters' preferences as an input, and returns the elected candidate for each issue. Multi-issue voting can take place offline or online:

  • In the offline setting, agents' preferences are known for all issues in advance. Therefore, the choices on all issues can be made simultaneously. This setting is often called public decision making.
  • In the online setting, the issues represent decisions in different times; each issue t occurs at time t. The voters' preferences for issue t become known only at time t. This setting is often called perpetual voting. A perpetual voting rule is a rule that, in each round t, takes as input the voters' preferences, as well as the sequence of winners in rounds 1,...,t-1, and returns an element of Ct that is elected in time t.
    • Some authors[6] distinguish between a semi-online setting, in which the number of rounds is known in advance and only the preferences in each round are unknown, and a full-online setting, in which even the number of rounds is unknown.

Cardinal preferences

[edit]

With cardinal ballots, each voter assigns a numeric utility to each alternative in each round. The total utility of a voter is the sum of utilities he assigns to the elected candidates in each round.

Offline cardinal ballots

[edit]

Conitzer, Freeman and Shah[1] studied multi-issue voting with offline cardinal ballots (they introduced the term public decision making). They focus on fairness towards individual agents. A natural fairness requirement in this setting is proportional division, by which each agent should receive at least 1/n of their maximum utility. Since proportionality might not be attainable, they suggest three relaxations:

  • Proportionality up to one issue (PROP1): for each voter, there exists a round such that, if the decision on that round would change to the voter's best candidate in that round, the voter would have his fair share.
  • Round robin share (RRS): each voter receives at least as much utility as he could attain if the rounds were divided by round-robin item allocation and he would play the last.
  • Pessimistic proportional share (PPS).

These relaxations make sense when the number of voters is small and the number of issues is large, so a difference of one issue is small w.r.t. 1/n. They show that the Maximum Nash Welfare solution (maximizing the product of all agents' utilities) satisfies or approximates all three relaxations. They also provide polynomial time algorithms and hardness results for finding allocations satisfying these axioms, with or without Pareto efficiency.

Online cardinal ballots

[edit]

Freeman, Zahedi and Conitzer[7] study multi-issue voting with online cardinal ballots. They present two greedy algorithms that aim to maximize the long-term Nash welfare (product of all agents' utilities). They evaluate their algorithms on data gathered from a computer systems application.

Approval preferences

[edit]

Offline approval voting: one candidate per round

[edit]

The simplest multi-issue voting setting is that there is a set of issues, and each agent votes either for or against each issue (effectively, there is a single candidate in each round). Amanatidis, Barrot, Lang, Markakis and Ries[8] present several voting rules for this setting, based on the Hamming distance:

  • The utilitarian rule (which they call "minisum") just follows the majority vote of each issue independently of the others, This rule may be unfair towards minorities, but it is strategyproof.
  • The egalitarian rule (which they call "minimax") accepts a subset of issues that minimizes the maximum Hamming distance to the voters' ballots (that is, minimizes disagreement). This rule might arguably give too much power to minorities; additionally, it is not strategyproof.
  • A family of rules based on Ordered weighted averaging can be used to interpolate between the utilitarian and egalitarian rule. This family allows to attain a trade-off between fairness towards minorities and strategyproofness.

Barrot, Lang and Yokoo[9] study the manipulability of these OWA-based rules. They prove that the only strategyproof OWA rule with non-increasing weights is the utilitarian rule. They also study empirically a sub-family of the OWA-based rules. Their family is characterized by a parameter p, which represents a property called "orness" of the OWA rule. p=0.5 yields utilitarian AV, whereas p=1 yields egalitarian AV. They show empirically that increasing p results in a larger fraction of random profiles that can be manipulated by at least one voter.

Freeman, Kahng and Pennock[10] study multiwinner approval voting with a variable number of winners. In fact, they treat each candidate as a binary issue (yes/no), so their setting can be seen as multi-issue voting with one candidate per round. They adapt the justified representation concepts to this setting as follows:

  • Each voter gains satisfaction, not only from an elected candidate that he approves, but also from a non-elected candidate that he does not approve (this makes the problem similar to multi-issue voting, where each candidate is a binary issue).
  • A group is L-large if it contains at least L*n/m voters (where m is the total number of candidates), and L-cohesive if in addition the group members agree on the placement of at least L candidates (that is: the intersection of Ai plus the intersection of C\Ai is at least L).
  • A committee is r-AS (r-average-satisfaction) if for every L-cohesive group, the average of the members' satisfaction is at least r*L. The JR, PJR and EJR conditions are generalized in a similar way.
  • The PAV rule chooses a committee that maximizes the sum of Harmonic(sati), where sati is the satisfaction of voter i. The sequential Phragmen rule and the method of equal shares divide the load of each elected candidate among the voters who approve it, and the load of each unelected candidate among the voters who do not approve it. All these rules satisfy PJR. MES violates EJR; it is not known whether the other two satisfy it.
  • A deterministic rule cannot guarantee r-AS for r = (m-1)/m+epsilon, for any epsilon>0. PAV, Phragmen and MES cannot guarantee r-AS for r = 1/2+epsilon. But there is a randomized rule that satisfies (29/32)-AS.

Skowron and Gorecki[11] study a similar setting: multi-issue voting with offline approval voting, where in each round t there is a single candidate (a single yes/no decision). Their main fairness axiom is proportionality: each group of size k should be able to influence at least a fraction k/n of the decisions. This is in contrast to justified-representation axioms, which consider only cohesive groups. This difference is important, since empirical studies show that cohesive groups are rare.[12] Formally, they define two fairness notions, for voting without abstentions:

  • Proportionality: in each group of size k, the utility of at least one voter should be larger than (m/2)*(k/n)-1. The multiplicative factor of 1/2 is essential; as a simple example, suppose n/2 voters always vote "yes" and the other n/2 voters always vote "no". Then, any fair rule must decide "yes" exactly m/2 times, so the utility of each voter would be m/2. Therefore, for the group of all voters (k=n), we cannot guarantee a higher utility than (m/2)*(k/n).
  • Proportional average representation: a function d(*) such that, in every group of voters with size k, the average satisfaction is at least d(k/n)

For voting with abstentions, the definitions must be adapted (since if all voters abstain in all issues, their utility will necessarily be 0): instead of m, the factor changes to the number of issues on which all group members do not abstain.

They study two rules:

  • Proportional approval voting (PAV) – without abstentions, it guarantees the maximum possible average representation, which is d(r)=(m/2)*r-1; this implies that it is proportional. Moreover, for cohesive groups it has average representation d(L) > 3L/4-1. It is proportional also in voting with abstentions.
  • and method of equal shares (MES) – without abstentions, it is proportional, and has average representation d(r)>((m+1)/3)*r-1. With abstentions, the naive implementation of MES is not proportional; but it has a variant that is proportional (the method of coordinated auctions with equal shares).

Teh, Elkind and Neoh[13] study utilitarian welfare and egalitarian welfare optimization in public decision making with approval preferencers.

Offline approval voting: multiple candidates per round

[edit]

Brill, Markakis, Papasotiropoulos and Jannik Peters[14] extended the results of Skowron and Gorecki to issues with multiple candidates per round, and possible dependencies between the issues; see below, the subsection on Fairness in combinatorial voting.

Page, Shapiro and Talmon[15] studied a special case in which the "issues" are cabinet offices. For each office, there is a set of candidates; all sets are pairwise disjoint. Each voter should vote for a single candidate per office. The goal is to elect a single minister per office. In contrast to the public decision-making setting,[1] here the number of voters is large and the number of issues is small. They present two generalizations of the justified representation property:

  • The weaker generalization is Global proporional justified representation (G-PJR): for every group S of agents of size Ln/k, whose approval sets in all offices have a non-empty intersection, there are at least L offices in which the elected candidate is approved by at least one member of S. A G-PJR allocation always exists (using a super-polynomial time cohesive-greedy algorithm), and it is fixed-parameter tractable w.r.t. the number of voters.
  • The stronger generalization is Partial proportional justified representation (P-PJR): for every group S of agents of size Ln/x, whose approval sets in some x out of k offices have a nonempty intersection, there are at least L offices in which the elected candidate is approved by at least one member of S. A P-PJR allocation always exists (using a super-polynomial time cohesive-greedy algorithm).

They generalize the setting by considering that different issues (offices) have different weight (importance, power). They consider both an objective power function, and subjective power functions. For an objective power function, they define a generalization of justified representation, which they call most important power allocation. They then present a greedy version of PAV, and show via simulations that it guarantees justified representation to minorities in many cases.

Online approval voting: multiple candidates per round

[edit]

In online approval voting, it is common to assume that in each round t there are multiple candidates; the set of candidates is denoted by Ct. Each voter j approves a subset of At,j of Ct.

Martin Lackner[2] studied perpetual voting with online approval ballots. He defined the following concepts:

  • The satisfaction of a voter is the number of rounds in which one of his approved candidates is elected.
  • The support of a voter in some round is the fraction of voters who support one of his approved candidates.
  • The quota of a voter is the sum of his supports over all previous round.

Based on these concepts, he defined three fairness axioms:

  1. Simple proportionality - in any simple instance, in which each agent votes for the same single candidate each time, the satisfaction of each agent should be at least his quota (this means that each group of voters, who support the same candidate, should have their candidate elected a number of times proportional to the group size).
  2. Independence of unanimous decisions: if there is an issue on which all voters agree, then the decision on this issue should not affect future decisions (this axiom prevents obvious manipulations by adding uncontroversial issues to the agenda).
  3. Bounded dry spells: for each voter should be satisfied with at least one decision in a given (bounded) time-period. The bound may depend on the number of voters.

He also defines two quantitative properties:

  1. Perpetual lower/upper quota compliance - the likelihood of a voter to be satisfied with a proportional fraction of the decisions;
  2. Gini coefficient of influence - the inequality in the degree of influence of different voters.

He defined a class of perpetual voting rules, called weighted approval voting. Each voter is assigned a weight, which is usually initialized to 1. At each round, the candidate with the highest sum of approving weights is elected (breaking ties by a fixed predefined order). The weights of voters who approved the winning candidate are decreased, and the weights of other voters are increased. Several common weighting schemes are:

  • Perpetual PAV - as in sequential proportional approval voting: the weight of a voter with current satisfaction k is 1/(k+1). It satisfies simple proportionality, but not bounded dry spells, nor any quota compliance.
  • Perpetual Unit-cost - the weight of a satisfied voter remains the same while the weight of an unsatisfied voter increases by 1. So the weight of a voter with current satisfaction k in time t is t-k.
  • Perpetual Reset - the weight of a satisfied voter drops to 1 while the weight of an unsatisfied voter increases by 1.
  • Perpetual Equality - the weight of a voter with satisfaction k is n-k. So the vote of a voter with satisfaction k is larger than all vote of voters with satisfaction larger than k.
  • Perpetual Consensus - the weight of an unsatisfied voter is increased by 1. The weights of all voters are increased by 1; then, the total weight of satisfied voters is decreased n (the weight of each satisfied voter decreases by n/s, where s is the number of satisfied voters). This rule achieves the best results in the axiomatic analysis: it is the only rule that satisfies all three axioms (simple proportionality, independence of unanimous decisions, and bounded dry spells: no agent has a dry spell of length (n2+3n)/4. This rule is related to an apportionment method of Frege.[3]
  • Perpetual Phragmen - Each round, the budget of each voter is increased continuously, until some group of voters can "purchase" a candidate. It satisfies simple proportionality and bounded dry spells: no agent has a dry spell of length 2n-1. This rule is related to Phragmen's voting rules. It can be computed in polynomial time.
  • Perpetual Quota - the weight of a voter is the difference between this voter's satisfaction and his quota. This rule satisfies simple proportionality and independence of unanimous decisions, but not bounded dry spell. However, it performs best in the experimental evaluation, in the two metrics: perpetual lower quota compliance and Gini coefficient of influence.
  • Perpetual Nash - maximizes the product of the voters' satisfaction scores.

Maly and Lackner[3] discuss general classes of simple perpetual voting rules for online approval ballots, and analyze the axioms that can be satisfied by rules of each class. In particular, they discuss Perpetual Phragmen, Perpetual Quota and Perpetual Consensus.

Bulteau, Hazon, Page, Rosenfeld and Talmon[4] focus on fairness notions to groups of voters, rather than to individual voters. They adapt some justified representation properties to this setting. In particular, they define two variants of proportional justified representation (PJR). In both variants, we say that a group of agents agree in round t if there is at least one candidate in Ct that they all approve.

  • The weaker variant is all-periods-intersection-PJR. It requires that, for every group S of agents of size Ln/T who agree in all T rounds, there are at least L rounds in which the elected candidate is approved by at least one member of S.
  • The stronger variant is some-periods-intersection-PJR. It requires that, for every group S of agents of size Ln/k who agree in some k out of T rounds, there are at least L rounds in which the elected candidate is approved by at least one member of S. This variant is stronger, as it does not require that the group agrees in all T rounds. However, if they agree on fewer rounds, then their "entitlement" is proportionately smaller.

They prove that these axioms can be satisfied both in the static setting (where voters' preferences are the same in each round) and in the dynamic setting (where voters' preferences may change between rounds). They also report a human study for identifying what outcomes are considered desirable in the eyes of ordinary people.

Chandak, Goel and Peters[6] strengthen both axioms from PJR to EJR (the difference is that, in EJR, there must be at least L rounds in which the elected candidate is approved by the same member of S). They call their new axioms "EJR" and "strong-EJR". They also adapt three voting rules to this setting:

  • The Sequential Phragmen rule is fully online - it makes decisions round by round, and does not need to know the total number of decisions. It works as follows. For each voter i, we keep a variable xi, which we call the load of i. Initially, all loads are set to 0. In each round t, for each candidate c in Ct, we check how to divide a total load of 1 among the voters who approve c in that round, such that the maximum total load assigned to a single voter will be as small as possible (figuratively, one can think of each voter as a bottle filled with xi liters of water; we have to pour 1 liter of water into the bottles that support c, such that the maximum water height will be as low as possible). In each round t, we choose the candidate for which the maximum total load is as small as possible. The rule can be computed in polynomial time. The rule can be computed in polynomial time.[3] It satisfies strong PJR (some-periods-intersection-PJR), but fails even weak EJR (all-periods-intersection-EJR).[6]: 4.1 
  • The method of equal shares is semi-online – it needs to know the total number of rounds, but still works round by round. For each voter i, we keep a variable bi, which we call the budget of i. Initially, all budgets are set to 1. In each round t, for each candidate c in Ct, we check how to divide a total cost of n/T among the voters who approve c in that round. We choose the candidate for which the maximum price that has to be paid is as small as possible. If, in some round t, no candidate is affordable by the voters who approve it, then we elect a candidate who minimizes the amount that has to be paid by voters who do not approve it, and zero the budget of voters who approve it. The rule can be computed in polynomial time. It satisfies weak-EJR, but fails strong-PJR (and strong-EJR).
  • Proportional Approval Voting is offline. It chooses the decision sequence that maximizes the PAV-score, which is the sum over all voters i of the Harmonic number of the number of elected candidates approved by i. It satisfies strong-EJR. Finding the optimal sequence is NP-hard; however, using local search, it is possible to find a locally-optimal sequence that satisfies strong-EJR too.
  • It remains open whether there exists a fully-online rule that satisfies EJR (it would imply the existence of an EJR rule that satisfies House monotonicity, which is another open problem).
  • Stronger variants of these properties, where groups of voters may have a slightly smaller size or agree on fewer rounds, may be impossible to satisfy.[6]: Sec.5 
  • They empirically compared various rules for their average utility (utilitarian value), 25% percentile utility (inspired by egalitarian value), and Gini coefficient. For the average utility, utilitarian approval voting is best; the order among proportional rules was: PAV > Seq.Phragmen > MES > Perpetual Quota > Perpetual Consensus, but the differences are small. For the egalitarian value and Gini coefficient, utilitarian approval voting is worst; there is no consistent difference between the proportional rules. The datasets were (a) random, (b) taken from USA voting data, (c) taken from machine-learning models trained on the Moral Machine dataset.

Perpetual multiwinner voting

[edit]

Bredereck, Fluschnik, and Kaczmarczyk[16] study perpetual multiwinner voting: at each round, each voter votes for a single candidate. The goal is to elect a committee of a given size. In addition, the difference between the new committee and the previous committee should be bounded: in the conservative model the difference is bounded from above (two consecutive committees should have a slight symmetric difference), and in the revolutionary model the difference is bounded from below (two successive committees should have a sizeable symmetric difference). Both models are NP-hard, even for a constant number of agents.

Combinatorial preferences

[edit]

One complication in multi-issue voting is that there may be dependencies between agents' preferences on different issues. For example, suppose the issues to be decided on are different kinds of food that may be given in a meal. Suppose the bread can be either black or white, and the main dish can be either hummus or tahini. An agent may want either black bread with hummus or white bread with tahini, but not the other way around. This problem is called non-separability.

Eliciting non-separable preferences

[edit]

There are several approaches for eliciting voters' preferences when they are not separable:

  1. If there are only few issues, it is possible to ask each voter to rank all possible combinations of candidates. However, the number of combinations increases exponentially in the number of issues, so it is not practical when there are many issues. There is some research on languages for concise representation of preferences.[17]
  2. It is possible to ask for each voters' favorite alternative in each issue separately. This option is simpler, but might lead to multiple-election paradoxes, where the collective decision is worst for all agents. For example, suppose there are three issues, and for each issue there are two candidates - 1 and 0. Suppose Alice's top choice is (1, 1, 0), Bob's top choice is (1, 0, 1), and Chana's top choice is (0, 1, 1), and all agents' last choice is (1, 1, 1). A majority voting in each issue separately would lead to the outcome (1,1,1), which is worst for all voters.[18]
  3. In sequential voting,[19][20] the issues are decided in order, so that each agent can vote on an issue based on the outcomes in previously-decided issues. This method is useful when there is a natural order of dependence on the issues. However, if some issues depend on decisions in future issues, the voters will have a hard time deciding what to vote.[21]
  4. In iterative voting,[22][23] we ask for each voters' favorite alternative in each issue separately, but allow them to revise their vote based on other people's votes. Voters are allowed to update only one issue at a time. The problem is that the iterative dynamics might not converge. However, in certain special cases, a Nash equilibrium exists.[5] Iterative voting can improve the social welfare and prevent some of the multiple-election paradoxes; this was shown both by computer simulations[24] and by laboratory experiments.[25]

A survey on voting in combinatorial domains is given by Lang and Xia, 2016.[26]

Fairness in combinatorial voting

[edit]

Brill, Markakis, Papasotiropoulos and Jannik Peters[14] study offline multi-issue voting with a non-binary domain, and possible dependencies between the issues, where the main goal is fair representation. They define generalizations of PAV and MES that handle conditional ballots; they call them conditional PAV and conditional MES. They prove that:

  • Under different assumptions, conditional-PAV and conditional-MES satisfy alpha-proportionality, for some alpha that depends on the maximum degree of the dependency graphs and the maximum number of candidates per issue.
  • Computing the winner of conditional-MES is NP-hard even when all voters have a common dependency graph; and when voters may have different depency graph, even when the in-degree of each dependency graph is constant. But with both common dependency graph and bounded in-degree, the outcome can be computed in polynomial time. The same holds if each connected component of the global dependency graph has at most a constant number of vertices.

Generalizations

[edit]

Participatory budgeting

[edit]

Lackner, Maly and Rey[27] extend the concept of perpetual voting to participatory budgeting. A city running PB every year may want to make sure that the outcomes are fair over time, not only in each individual application.

Fair allocation of indivisible public goods

[edit]

In fair allocation of indivisible public goods (FAIPG), society has to choose a set of indivisible public goods, where there is are feasibility constraints on what subsets of elements can be chosen. Fain, Munagala and Shah[28] focus on three types of constraints:

  • Matroid constraints: there is a fixed matroid M over the items, and the chosen items must form a basis of M. This problem of fair public decision making[1] is a special case in which each issue is a category (containing all candidates for that issue), and there is partition matroid constraint such that a single candidate must be selected for each issue.
  • Matching constraints: there is a fixed graph G=(V,E), where the items are the edges, and the chosen items must form a matching in G.
  • Packing constraints: there is a fixed matrix A and a fixed vector b, and the indicator vector of the items x must satisfy the inequality A xb. The problem of participatory budgeting is a special case in which the matrix A has a single row containing the item costs, and b is the budget. Packing constraints allow a more general budgeting setting, in which there are different kinds of resources, each of which has a different budget.

Fain, Munagala and Shah[28] present a fairness notion for FAIPG, based on the core. They provide polynomial-time algorithms finding an additive approximation to the core, with a tiny multiplicative loss. With matroid constraints, the additive approximation is 2. With matching constraints, there is a constant additive bound. With packing constraints, with mild restrictions, the additive approximation is logarithmic in the width of the polytope. The algorithms are based on the convex program for maximizing the Nash social welfare.

Garg, Kulkarni and Murhekar[29] study FAIPG with budget constraints. They show polynomial-time reductions for the solutions of maximum Nash welfare and leximin, between the models of private goods, public goods, and public decision making. They prove that Max Nash Welfare allocations are Prop1, RRS and Pareto-efficient. However, finding such allocations as well as leximin allocations is NP-hard even with constantly many agents, or binary valuations. They design pseudo-polynomial time algorithms for computing an exact MNW or leximin-optimal allocation for constantly many agents, and for constantly many goods with additive valuations. They alsao present an O(n)-factor approximation for max Nash welfare, which also satisfies RRS, Prop1, and 1/2-Prop.

Banerjee, Gkatzelis, Hossain, Jin, Micah and Shah[30] study FAIPG with predictions: in each round, a public good arrives, each agent reveals his value for the good, and the algorithm should decide how much to invest in the good (subject to a total budget constraint). There are approximate predictions of each agent's total value for all goods. The goal is to attain proportional fairness for groups. With binary valuations and unit budget, proportional fairness can be achieved without predictions. With general valuations and budget, predictions are necessary to achieve proportional fairness.

Strategic manipulation

[edit]

Multi-issue voting rules are prone to strategic manipulation. A particularly simple form of manipulation is the Free-rider problem: some voters may untruthfully oppose a popular opinion in one issue, in order to receive increased consideration in other issues. Lackner, Maly and Nardi[31] study this problem in detail. They show that:

  • Almost every rule based on Ordered weighted averaging or on Thiele's rules, either using global optimization or sequential greedy elections, are prone to free-riding. The only exception is the utilitarian rule, which is not fair towards minorities.
  • For OWA or Thiele rule based on global optimization (except the utilitarian rule), it is NP-hard to compute the outcome; moreover, even when the winner of an issue is known, it is NP-hard to determine whether free-riding is possible (that is, whether a single agent can remove his approval from the winner without changing the winner). However, free-riding can never be harmful.
  • For sequential OWA and Thiele rules, computing the winner of each issue can be done in polynomial time, and hence it is easy to know whether free-riding is possible. However, free-riding in one issue may decrease the utility of the free-rider in the following issues; it is NP-hard to tell whether or not this will happen, and requires full information about all issues. Without complete information, it is impossible to know for sure whether free-riding is beneficial or harmful.
  • Simulation experiments consider variants of OWA and Thiele rules parameterized by a factor x; x=0 is the utilitarian rule, and larger x means that the rule is fairer. As x increases, the proportion of voters who can benefit from free-riding increases from 0 to about 50%; but the proportion of voters who can lose from free-riding increases too, from 0 to more than 10%.

See also

[edit]
  • Multiwinner voting
  • Storable votes - another way in which minorities can get a fair share of power - by strategically storing votes and spending them later.
  • Dynamic voting[32][33] - single-issue voting, in which the voters' preferences change over time.
  • Discursive dilemma - a contradiction between majority decisions on each issue separately, and majority decisions on the final outcome.
[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d Conitzer, Vincent; Freeman, Rupert; Shah, Nisarg (2017-06-20). "Fair Public Decision Making". Proceedings of the 2017 ACM Conference on Economics and Computation. EC '17. New York, NY, USA: Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 629–646. arXiv:1611.04034. doi:10.1145/3033274.3085125. ISBN 978-1-4503-4527-9. S2CID 30188911.
  2. ^ a b Lackner, Martin (2020-04-03). "Perpetual Voting: Fairness in Long-Term Decision Making". Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 34 (2): 2103–2110. doi:10.1609/aaai.v34i02.5584. ISSN 2374-3468. S2CID 209527302.
  3. ^ a b c d Lackner, Martin; Maly, Jan (2021-04-30). "Perpetual Voting: The Axiomatic Lens". arXiv:2104.15058 [cs.GT].
  4. ^ a b Bulteau, Laurent; Hazon, Noam; Page, Rutvik; Rosenfeld, Ariel; Talmon, Nimrod (2021). "Justified Representation for Perpetual Voting". IEEE Access. 9: 96598–96612. Bibcode:2021IEEEA...996598B. doi:10.1109/ACCESS.2021.3095087. ISSN 2169-3536. S2CID 235966019.
  5. ^ a b Ahn, David S.; Oliveros, Santiago (2012). "Combinatorial Voting". Econometrica. 80 (1): 89–141. doi:10.3982/ECTA9294. ISSN 0012-9682. JSTOR 41336582.
  6. ^ a b c d Chandak, Nikhil; Goel, Shashwat; Peters, Dominik (2023). "Proportional Aggregation of Preferences for Sequential Decision Making". arXiv:2306.14858 [cs.GT].
  7. ^ Freeman, Rupert; Zahedi, Seyed Majid; Conitzer, Vincent (2017-08-19). Fair and efficient social choice in dynamic settings. Melbourne, Australia: AAAI Press. pp. 4580–4587. ISBN 978-0-9992411-0-3.
  8. ^ Amanatidis, Georgios; Barrot, Nathanaël; Lang, Jérôme; Markakis, Evangelos; Ries, Bernard (2015-05-04). Multiple Referenda and Multiwinner Elections Using Hamming Distances: Complexity and Manipulability. Richland, SC: International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems. pp. 715–723. ISBN 978-1-4503-3413-6.
  9. ^ Barrot, Nathanaël; Lang, Jérôme; Yokoo, Makoto (2017-05-08). "Manipulation of Hamming-based Approval Voting for Multiple Referenda and Committee Elections". Richland, SC: International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems: 597–605. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  10. ^ Freeman, Rupert; Kahng, Anson; Pennock, David M. (2021-01-07). Proportionality in approval-based elections with a variable number of winners. Yokohama, Yokohama, Japan. pp. 132–138. ISBN 978-0-9992411-6-5.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  11. ^ Skowron, Piotr; Górecki, Adrian (2022-06-28). "Proportional Public Decisions". Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 36 (5): 5191–5198. doi:10.1609/aaai.v36i5.20454. ISSN 2374-3468. S2CID 250293245.
  12. ^ Bredereck, Robert; Faliszewski, Piotr; Kaczmarczyk, Andrzej; Niedermeier, Rolf (2019-08-10). An experimental view on committees providing justified representation. Macao, China: AAAI Press. pp. 109–115. ISBN 978-0-9992411-4-1.
  13. ^ Elkind, Edith; Neoh, Tzeh Yuan; Teh, Nicholas (2024), "Temporal Elections: Welfare, Strategyproofness, and Proportionality", ECAI 2024, IOS Press, pp. 3292–3299, retrieved 2024-10-30
  14. ^ a b https://www.ijcai.org/proceedings/2023/0282.pdf
  15. ^ Page, Rutvik; Shapiro, Ehud; Talmon, Nimrod (2020). "Electing the Executive Branch". arXiv:2009.09734 [cs.MA].
  16. ^ Bredereck, Robert; Fluschnik, Till; Kaczmarczyk, Andrzej (July 2022). "When Votes Change and Committees Should (Not)" (PDF). Proceedings of the Thirty-First International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. pp. 144–150. doi:10.24963/ijcai.2022/21. ISBN 978-1-956792-00-3. S2CID 250636565. Retrieved 27 April 2023.
  17. ^ Lang, Jérôme (2007-01-06). "Vote and aggregation in combinatorial domains with structured preferences". Proceedings of the 20th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. IJCAI'07. San Francisco, CA, USA: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc.: 1366–1371.
  18. ^ Lacy, Dean; Niou, Emerson M.S. (2000-01-01). "A Problem with Referendums". Journal of Theoretical Politics. 12 (1): 5–31. doi:10.1177/0951692800012001001. ISSN 0951-6298. S2CID 153344141.
  19. ^ Lang, Jérôme; Xia, Lirong (2009-05-01). "Sequential composition of voting rules in multi-issue domains". Mathematical Social Sciences. 57 (3): 304–324. doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2008.12.010. ISSN 0165-4896. S2CID 35194669.
  20. ^ Xia, Lirong; Conitzer, Vincent; Lang, Jérôme (2011-06-05). "Strategic sequential voting in multi-issue domains and multiple-election paradoxes". Proceedings of the 12th ACM conference on Electronic commerce. EC '11. New York, NY, USA: Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 179–188. doi:10.1145/1993574.1993602. ISBN 978-1-4503-0261-6. S2CID 6105649.
  21. ^ Conitzer, Vincent; Lang, Jérôme; Xia, Lirong (2009-07-11). "How hard is it to control sequential elections via the agenda?". San Francisco, CA, USA: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc.: 103–108. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  22. ^ Meir, Reshef; Polukarov, Maria; Rosenschein, Jeffrey; Jennings, Nicholas (2010-07-04). "Convergence to Equilibria in Plurality Voting". Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 24 (1): 823–828. doi:10.1609/aaai.v24i1.7624. ISSN 2374-3468. S2CID 15254323.
  23. ^ Kavner, Joshua; Meir, Reshef; Rossi, Francesca; Xia, Lirong (2023-01-20). "Convergence of Multi-Issue Iterative Voting under Uncertainty". arXiv:2301.08873 [cs.GT].
  24. ^ Bowman, Clark; Hodge, Jonathan K.; Yu, Ada (2014-06-01). "The potential of iterative voting to solve the separability problem in referendum elections". Theory and Decision. 77 (1): 111–124. doi:10.1007/s11238-013-9383-2. ISSN 1573-7187. S2CID 255110514.
  25. ^ Grandi, Umberto; Lang, Jérôme; Ozkes, Ali I.; Airiau, Stéphane (2022-12-10). "Voting behavior in one-shot and iterative multiple referenda". Social Choice and Welfare. doi:10.1007/s00355-022-01436-0. ISSN 1432-217X.
  26. ^ Lang, Jérôme; Xia, Lirong (2016). "Voting in Combinatorial Domains". Handbook of Computational Social Choice. pp. 197–222. doi:10.1017/CBO9781107446984.010. ISBN 9781107060432.
  27. ^ Lackner, Martin; Maly, Jan; Rey, Simon (2021-05-03). Fairness in Long-Term Participatory Budgeting. Richland, SC: International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems. pp. 1566–1568. ISBN 978-1-4503-8307-3.
  28. ^ a b Fain, Brandon; Munagala, Kamesh; Shah, Nisarg (2018-06-11). "Fair Allocation of Indivisible Public Goods". Proceedings of the 2018 ACM Conference on Economics and Computation. EC '18. New York, NY, USA: Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 575–592. doi:10.1145/3219166.3219174. ISBN 978-1-4503-5829-3. S2CID 3331859.
  29. ^ Garg, Jugal; Kulkarni, Pooja; Murhekar, Aniket (2021-07-21). "On Fair and Efficient Allocations of Indivisible Public Goods". arXiv:2107.09871 [cs.GT].
  30. ^ Banerjee, Siddhartha; Gkatzelis, Vasilis; Hossain, Safwan; Jin, Billy; Micha, Evi; Shah, Nisarg (2022-09-30). "Proportionally Fair Online Allocation of Public Goods with Predictions". arXiv:2209.15305 [cs.GT].
  31. ^ Lackner, Maly and Nardi. "Free-Riding in Multi-Issue Decisions". Proceedings of AAMAS 2023.
  32. ^ Tennenholtz, Moshe (2004-05-17). "Transitive voting". Proceedings of the 5th ACM conference on Electronic commerce. EC '04. New York, NY, USA: Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 230–231. doi:10.1145/988772.988808. ISBN 978-1-58113-771-2. S2CID 10062678.
  33. ^ Parkes, David; Procaccia, Ariel (2013-06-30). "Dynamic Social Choice with Evolving Preferences". Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 27 (1): 767–773. doi:10.1609/aaai.v27i1.8570. ISSN 2374-3468. S2CID 12490400.
  34. ^ Elkind, Edith; Obraztsova, Svetlana; Teh, Nicholas (2024-03-24). "Temporal Fairness in Multiwinner Voting". Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 38 (20): 22633–22640. arXiv:2312.04417. doi:10.1609/aaai.v38i20.30273. ISSN 2374-3468.