Democracy in classical Iran
Early Iranians had their own regional elected councils. By the time of the Medians, the city-states were administered in a democratic fashion.
During the Achaemenids, in a debate over the constitution of Iran, Otanes argued in favor of democracy, however he did not succeed. He enumerated five characteristic marks of the democracy: 1, an equality of rights for all; 2, the rejection of arbitrary power as ordinarily exercised by eastern princes; 3, appointment to offices by lot; 4, responsibility in office; 5, deliberation in common, and the framing of laws in popular assemblies.
By the time of Parthians, the appointment of kings was through election in the Parthian parliament, Megisthanes. In this way the king could be the representative of the whole nation.
Early Iranians
[edit]Regional elected councils are well documented particularly in the Indo-Iranian societies.[1]
Zoroaster's Gathas states that in order to bring peace, prosperity, stability, progress and happiness to the living world, people are to select only competent persons.[1] Song 16 is particularly dedicated to "Vohû Khshathra Vairya," literally "Good Domain Worthy-of-Choice." It shows that an ideal government must be an elected one.[1]
In its most sacred prayer the Ahunavar (Choice of the Lord), Zoroastrians are taught that their Lord and leader are to be chosen, through a Good Mind and only on account of their individual righteousness. This sets the basis for a spiritual and political democracy as far back as nearly four millennia ago.[2]
Zoroaster, the Iranian prophet advised people to listen to all parties and to choose the best of them. He said (Yasna 30, paragraph 2) "O people, listen to others and accept the best of them, and consider them with a bright and deep thinking. Every man and woman should chose the path of good and bad by his/her own."[3][4][5] He did not discriminate between man and woman in this regard and counted them equally.[5] In Yasna 30, he said "hearken with your ears to these best counsels, Reflect upon them with illumined judgment. Let each one choose his creed with that freedom of choice each must have at great events. O ye, be awake to these, my announcements."[6]
Medes
[edit]Diodorus mentions that after the Assyrians had ruled Asia for five hundred years "they were conquered by the Medes, and thereafter no king arose for many generations to lay claim to supreme power, but the city-states, enjoying a regimen of their own, were administered in a democratic fashion".[7][8]
Herodotus writes "After Assyrians had ruled upper Asia for five hundred and twenty years, the Medes were the first who began to revolt from them. These, it would seem, proved their bravery in fighting for freedom against the Assyrians; they cast off their slavery and won freedom. Afterwards, the other subject nations, too, did the same as the Medes. All of those on the mainland were now free men; but they came to be ruled by monarchs again, as I will now relate. There was among the Medes a clever man called Deioces: he was the son of Phraortes. Deioces was infatuated with sovereignty, and so he set about gaining it. Already a notable man in his own town (one of the many towns into which Media was divided), he began to profess and practice justice more constantly and zealously than ever, and he did this even though he knew that injustice is always the enemy of justice. Then the Medes of the same town, seeing his behavior, chose him to be their judge, and he (for he coveted sovereign power) was honest and just. By acting so, he won no small praise from his fellow townsmen, to such an extent that when the men of the other towns learned that Deioces alone gave fair judgments (having before suffered from unjust decisions), they came often and gladly to plead before Deioces; and at last they would submit to no arbitration but his. The number of those who came grew ever greater, for they heard that each case turned out in accord with the truth. Then Deioces seeing that everything now depend on him, would not sit in his former sear of judgment, and said he would give no more decisions; for it was of no advantage to him (he said) to leave his own business and spend all day judging the cases of his neighbors. This caused robbery and lawlessness to increase greatly in the towns; and, gathering together, the Medes conferred about their present affairs, and said (here, as IP suppose, the main speakers were Deioces' friends), 'since we cannot go on living in the present way in the land, come, let us set up a king over us; in this way the land will be well governed, and we ourselves shall attend to our business and not be routed by lawlessness.' With such words they persuaded themselves to be ruled by a king." [9][10][11] So in this way people were electing their kings.[11]
Achaemenids
[edit]Herodotus puts great emphasis on the fact that the proposals put forward included the idea of establishing "democracy" in Persia.[12] Herodotus in Histories gives an account on a debate over the constitution of Iran (Persia) in 522 BC, where Otanes argued in favor of democracy,[13][14] the principle of equality before the law,[15] and the accountable government.[16][17] He advocates a complete democracy,[18] on the grounds that under a democratic system "offices of state are exercised by lot".[19]
In that session, Otanes also talked about the disadvantages of monarchy.[20] He notes that democratic rule does not share any of the malice of a tyranny.[21] Otanes was one of the seven members who overthrew Gaumata.[22][23]
He recommended that the management of public affairs should be entrusted to the whole nation. He said, "it seems advisable, that we should no longer have a single man to rule over us. the rule of one is neither good nor pleasant... How indeed is it possible that monarchy should be a well-adjusted thing, when it allows a man to do as he likes without being answerable?... I vote, therefore, that we do away with monarchy, and raise the people to power. For the people are all in all."[24][25][26]
Otanes seems to find democracy inherently more equitable: "the rule of many has first a name attaching to it which is the fairest of all names, that is to say 'Equality.'"[19][27][28][29][30] Popular government ensures moderate rule, he suggests.[31]
The book "The Archaic Smile of Herodotus" notes that "in arguing that democracy will be good for Persia, Otanes contradicts himself, for he proposes to change the traditional form of government. This violation of ancient custom is just the practice of which he accuses tyrants."[32] However Otanes was advocating a return to the equality and democracy that was customary in ancient Persia. So violation of these customs was what he was accusing tyrants about.[33] Perhaps Otanes considered democracy reflecting Persia's tribal roots.[34]
Even though Otanes has not used the term demokratia in his speech, but his emphasis on equality under the law, elections by lot, and collective decisions makes it clear that he represents the democratic viewpoint.[35] Some scholars have gone further by considering that not only Otanes was in fact advocating the democracy, but also "a pretty radical form of it".[36]
Some scholars have tended to equate Otanes' arguments with those of the author himself (Herodotus).[37] Others have titled Otanes as "the champion of democracy".[38]
According to Aristotle the three parts of a politeia are the deliberative, the magistracies, and the judiciary. This tripartite structure of the politeia was a traditional idea; Aristotle only elaborated upon it. The threefold division is already evident in Otanes' defence of democracy, where he defends democracy for its virtues in all three areas.[39]
From the viewpoint of the methodological approach, Otanes provided a "practical example" of Cambyses, that how he acted as a monarch in power.[citation needed] The moral force of Otanes' argument derives from his conviction that monarchy and oligarchy have proven untrustworthy, insofar as natural vanity is bound to corrupt even good individuals if left unchecked.[31][38]
In addition to book 3, later in book 6 Herodotus once again insists that the account of the debate is historical, and he vents his spleen at those who deny that Otanes advised the Persians to demokrateesthai.[40][41]
Arsacids
[edit]At the time of Parthians, kings held absolute power over succession but were still greatly influenced by the Parthian parliament, Magistan (in Greek: Megisthanes). The parliament was of two parts: one of the wise men and magi from across the country, and the second the relatives of the royal family.[42][43]
The two parts separately and together, formed three different councils. A third could be assembled, as the result of emergencies, comprising the members of two other councils. This council (comprising the two) was called the Megisthanes.[44] Strabo writes that "the Council of the Parthians, according to Poseidonius, consists of two groups, one that of kinsmen, and the other that of wise men and Magi, from both of which groups the kings were appointed."[45][46][47] The "wise men" in the parliament typically exceeded the magi.[48]
Megisthanes was the first parliament of Iran.[49][50] The first session of the Megisthanes parliament, was held in Nowruz of the year 137 BC, where Mithridates I personally attended the council.[51] It can be concluded that the Parthian parliament was the result of the achievements of past civilizations specially the Achaemenids (whose royal courts were similar to the Parthian councils) and Greeks.[52] Justin (41.2.2) proclaims this parliament a senate in Parthia.[53][54][55] Tacitus states that the parliament was composed of 300 of the rich and wise men. The people had somewhat of a voice in the parliament. As long as the parliament and people had consensus, they the Parthian kings would have to respect their advice. However, with fracturing disagreements, council political parties could often form. Artabanus III's removal and reinstallation are an example of the council's power and show the role of the parliament in reinstating the king's power, or taking it away. Much of the aristocratic group in the council comprised the Seven Great Houses of Iran, continuing the Achaemenid tradition. This tradition would continue from the Achaemenid dynasty to the Sassanids as a key aspect of the court.[56][57] Over the same provoke, in wake of eras there had appeared conflicting views towards its constituent structure and naming conventions. Some abstractive attempts have compared the bicameral congress of both ensembles with Majlis, while considering the ensemble of wise experienced men to be Mahestan, and the ensemble of royals and religious influentials as Moghestan.[58]
The Parthian kingdom was not solely based on absolutism, but there was a parliament of sorts where important issues were being resolved discussed.[52][59] While there is no concrete evidence for either an election of the king or a true separation of powers between the monarchy and the council, the dynamics of the royal court and the kings' necessity to please the Seven Great Houses of Iran guarantee that for the king to interfere with the council would have been a disastrous political move.[60] Justin considers one of the reasons for the collapse of Parthian empire to be the power of this council and the extreme actions of its members.[56]
References
[edit]- ^ a b c "ZOROASTRIAN RELIGION AND DEMOCRACY". zoroastrian.org. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Zoroastrian sacred text: the holy book of avesta". persepolis.nu. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Yasna 30, paragraph 2
- ^ "AVESTA: YASNA: Sacred Liturgy and Gathas/Hymns of Zarathushtra". avesta.org. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ a b "اشوزرتشت نخستین پیام آور دموکراسی و حقوق بشر در جهان". tarikhfa (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Ahunuvaiti Gatha: Yasna 30". Zarathushtra. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Diodorus 9.20
- ^ "Diodorus Siculus, Library, Fragments of Book 9, Chapter 20". Perseus. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Herodotus, Histories, 1.96
- ^ Herodotus (2013). Delphi Complete Works of Herodotus (Illustrated) Volume 5 of Delphi Ancient Classics. Delphi Classics. ISBN 9781909496453.
- ^ a b "دموکراسی در تاریخ کهن ایران". melimazhabi (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Canfora, Luciano (2008). Democracy in Europe: A History of an Ideoloy Volume 5 of Making of Europe. John Wiley & Sons. p. 21. ISBN 9781405154598.
- ^ "Otanes". Livius.org. Livius. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Otanes of Persia". rpi.edu. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Otanes". Encyclopaedia Iranica. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Democracy in Herodotus, Democracy in America". columbia.edu. Columbia College. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Maloy, J. S. (2008). The Colonial American Origins of Modern Democratic Thought. Cambridge University Press. pp. 28. ISBN 9781139473477.
- ^ Höffe, Otfried (2003). Aristotle SUNY series in Ancient Greek Philosophy. SUNY Press. p. 178. ISBN 9780791456347.
- ^ a b "Ancient Greece's Legacy for Liberty: Herodotus and the Way of Otanes". libertarianism.org. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "اوتانه". تارنمای تخصصی تاریخ ایران (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Martin, Brad (Fall 2011). "Herodotus, Politics and Athenian Democracy" (PDF). Xavier Journal of Politics. 2: 46–52. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-10-22. Retrieved 2016-09-02.
- ^ "تاریخچه نوروز باستانی از نگاهی دیگر". BBC Persian. BBC. 22 March 2010. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ E. McCarthy, George (2009). Dreams in Exile: Rediscovering Science and Ethics in Nineteenth-Century Social Theory. SUNY Press. p. 59. ISBN 9781438425979.
- ^ "Herodotus: 3.80-97". The Latin Library. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "The History of Herodotus". Sacred Texts. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Herodotus: Book three". Reed. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Introduction: Measures of Democratization" (PDF). prio.org. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Brock, Roger; Hodkinson, Stephen (2002). Alternatives to Athens: Varieties of Political Organization and Community in Ancient Greece Varieties of Political Organization and Community in Ancient. Oxford University Press. p. 105. ISBN 9780199258109.
- ^ A. Raaflaub, Kurt; Ober, Josiah; Wallace, Robert (2007). Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece Joan Palevsky Imprint in Classical Literature. University of California Press. p. 158. ISBN 9780520932173.
- ^ Hart, John (2014). Herodotus and Greek History (Routledge Revivals). Routledge. p. 71. ISBN 9781317678380.
- ^ a b Monoson, S. Sara (2000). Plato's Democratic Entanglements: Athenian Politics and the Practice of Philosophy. Princeton University Press. p. 121. ISBN 9781400823741.
- ^ Flory, Stewart (1987). The Archaic Smile of Herodotus. Wayne State University Press. p. 132. ISBN 9780814318270.
- ^ Canfora, Luciano (2008). Democracy in Europe: A History of an Ideoloy Volume 5 of Making of Europe. John Wiley & Sons. p. 21. ISBN 9781405154598.
- ^ Butler, Clark (2008). Human Rights Ethics: A Rational Approach Purdue (human rights studies series). Purdue University Press. p. 54. ISBN 9781557534804.
- ^ "Freedom and Power in Classical Athens" (PDF). washington.edu. University of Washington. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Cartledge, Paul (2016). Democracy: A Life. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780190494322.
- ^ Krieger Balot, Ryan (2001). Greed and Injustice in Classical Athens. Princeton University Press. p. 116. ISBN 9780691048550.
- ^ a b Ward, L.; King, Bruce (2014). Modern Democracy and the Theological-Political Problem in Spinoza, Rousseau, and Jefferson Recovering Political Philosophy. Springer. p. 10. ISBN 9781137475053.
- ^ Clausen, Wendell (1981). Harvard Studies in Classical Philology (Volume 94 of Harvard Studies in Classical Philology Series). Harvard University Press. pp. 159–160. ISBN 9780674379428.
- ^ Herodotus, Histories, 6.43.3
- ^ Tolbert Roberts, Jennifer (2011). Athens on Trial: The Antidemocratic Tradition in Western Thought. Princeton University Press. ISBN 9781400821327.
- ^ "مهستان، نخستین مجلس رسمی ایرانیان". Ghatreh (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Who were the Magi?". fivedoves.com. 13 Dec 2010. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "اشکانیان". roshd.ir (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Strabo, Geographica, book 11, chapter 9, section 3
- ^ "Strabo, Geography". Perseus. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "Strabo, Geography". Perseus. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Pirnia, Hassan. Tarikh-e Iran-e Bastan (Volume 3). Tehran: Majles. p. 2234.
- ^ "تاریخچه مجلس در ایران؛ از مهستان تا بهارستان". TarikhIrani (in Persian). تاریخ ایرانی. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "نگاهی به تاریخچه مجلس در ایران". basironline (in Persian). بصیر آنلاین. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "مهستان، نخستین مجلس رسمی ایرانیان". Ilna (in Persian). ایلنا: خبرگزاری کار ایران. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ a b "نگاهی به مجلسهای ایران در دوران اشکانی". Kheradgan (in Persian). Archived from the original on 13 September 2016. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Epitome of the Philippic History of Pompeius Trogus, Justin, book 41, section 2, part 2
- ^ "واژه (مهستان) یادگاری از مجالس باستان". ParsianDej (in Persian). پارسیان دژ. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ کریستنسن, آرتور (1388). ایران در زمان ساسانیان (in Persian). تهران: راستی نو. p. 36.
- ^ a b "مقایسه مجلس مهستان دوره اشکانی با مجلس اول مشروطه". JameJamOnline (in Persian). Archived from the original on 22 October 2016. Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ "اشكانيان كه بودند". IranAtlas (in Persian). Retrieved 2 September 2016.
- ^ Khamseh, Mohammad. "Mahestan and Moghestan: An etymologic regrouping for better figuring out the Arsacids parliament". Medium. Retrieved 20 November 2023.
- ^ پیرنیا, حسن (1306). ایران باستان (جلد ۱) (in Persian). تهران: مجلس. p. 257.
- ^ پیرنیا, حسن (1306). ایران باستان. جلد 3 (in Persian). تهران: مجلس. p. 2233.