Jump to content

Biological constraints

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Biological Constraints)

Biological constraints are factors which make populations resistant to evolutionary change. One proposed definition of constraint is "A property of a trait that, although possibly adaptive in the environment in which it originally evolved, acts to place limits on the production of new phenotypic variants."[1] Constraint has played an important role in the development of such ideas as homology and body plans.

Types of constraint

[edit]

Any aspect of an organism that has not changed over a certain period of time could be considered to provide evidence for "constraint" of some sort. To make the concept more useful, it is therefore necessary to divide it into smaller units. First, one can consider the pattern of constraint as evidenced by phylogenetic analysis and the use of phylogenetic comparative methods; this is often termed phylogenetic inertia, or phylogenetic constraint. It refers to the tendency of related taxa sharing traits based on phylogeny. Charles Darwin spoke of this concept in his 1859 book "On the Origin of Species", as being "Unity of Type" and went on to explain the phenomenon as existing because organisms do not start over from scratch, but have characteristics that are built upon already existing ones that were inherited from their ancestors; and these characteristics likely limit the amount of evolution seen in that new taxa due to these constraints.[2]

If one sees particular features of organisms that have not changed over rather long periods of time (many generations), then this could suggest some constraint on their ability to change (evolve). However, it is not clear that mere documentation of lack of change in a particular character is good evidence for constraint in the sense of the character being unable to change. For example, long-term stabilizing selection related to stable environments might cause stasis. It has often been considered more fruitful, to consider constraint in its causal sense: what are the causes of lack of change?

Stabilizing selection

[edit]

The most common explanation for biological constraint is that stabilizing selection acts on an organism to prevent it changing, for example, so that it can continue to function in a tightly-defined niche. This may be considered to be a form of external constraint, in the sense that the organism is constrained not by its makeup or genetics, but by its environment. The implication would be that if the population was in a new environment, its previously constrained features would potentially begin to evolve.

Functional coupling and physico-chemical constraint

[edit]

Related to the idea of stabilizing selection is that of the requirement that organisms function adequately in their environment. Thus, where stabilizing selection acts because of the particular niche that is occupied, mechanical and physico-chemical constraints act in a more general manner. For example, the acceleration caused by gravity places constraints on the minimum bone density and strength for an animal of a particular size. Similarly, the properties of water mean that tissues must have certain osmotic properties in order to function properly.

Functional coupling takes the idea that organisms are integrated networks of functional interactions (for example, the vertebral column of vertebrates is involved in the muscle, nerve, and vascular systems as well as providing support and flexibility) and therefore cannot be radically altered without causing severe functional disruption. This may be viewed as one type of trade-off. As Rupert Riedl pointed out, this degree of functional constraint — or burden — generally varies according to position in the organism. Structures literally in the centre of the organism — such as the vertebral column — are often more burdened than those at the periphery, such as hair or toes.

Lack of genetic variation and developmental integration

[edit]

This class of constraint depends on certain types of phenotype not being produced by the genotype (compare stabilizing selection, where there is no constraint on what is produced, but rather on what is naturally selected). For example, for a highly homozygous organism, the degree of observed phenotypic variability in its descendants would be lower than those of a heterozygous one. Similarly, developmental systems may be highly canalised, to prevent the generation of certain types of variation.

Relationships of constraint classes

[edit]

Although they are separate, the types of constraints discussed are nevertheless relatable to each other. In particular, stabilizing selection, mechanical, and physical constraints might lead through time to developmental integration and canalisation. However, without any clear idea of any of these mechanisms, deducing them from mere patterns of stasis as deduced from phylogenetic patterns or the fossil record remains problematic.[3] In addition, the terminology used to describe constraints has led to confusion.[4]

Examples

[edit]

Variational inaccessibility. Despite mutations, certain character variants are never produced. These variants are therefore developmentally impossible to achieve and are never introduced into a population. This is implied by canalization and has been called both genetic and developmental constraint.”[5]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Blomberg, S. P.; Garland, T. (2002). "Tempo and mode in evolution: Phylogenetic inertia, adaptation and comparative methods". Journal of Evolutionary Biology. 15 (6): 899–910. doi:10.1046/j.1420-9101.2002.00472.x. S2CID 16027791.
  2. ^ Darwin, Charles (1859). "Ch. 6". On The Origin of Species.
  3. ^ Brakefield, P. M.; Roskam, J. C. (2006). "Exploring Evolutionary Constraints is a Task for an Integrative Evolutionary Biology". The American Naturalist. 168: S4–S13. doi:10.1086/509049. PMID 17109328. S2CID 40495719.
  4. ^ Antonovics, Janis; Van Tienderen, Peter H. (1991). "Ontoecogenophyloconstraints? The chaos of constraint terminology". Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 6 (5): 166–168. doi:10.1016/0169-5347(91)90059-7. PMID 21232448.
  5. ^ Schwenk K, Wagner GP (2003) "Constraint". In: Hall BK, Olson WM (eds) Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (MA), pp. 52–61. ISBN 9780674022409

Further reading

[edit]
  • Garland, Jr., T., C. J. Downs, and A. R. Ives. (2022). Trade-offs (and constraints) in organismal biology. Physiological and Biochemical Zoology 95, 82–112.
  • Riedl, R. (1978). Order in Living organisms: a systems analysis of evolution. John Wiley & Sons.
  • Schwenk, K. (1995). A utilitarian approach to evolutionary constraint. Zoology 98, 251-262.